Skip to main content

Berkeley on Calculus

Image result for baseball diamond

As is well known (at least in certain nerdy circles), the immaterialist philosopher George Berkeley sharply criticized Isaac Newton, and the branch of mathematics Newton had founded, in 1734. Berkeley's book of that year, THE ANALYST, said that calculus depends upon presuming that an "infinitesimal" is something at a certain point in one's reason, then assuming it is nothing at another point. That is internally incoherent.

Berkeley thus earned himself a place within the usual story about calculus. The story goes -- Newton proposed certain rough-and-ready ideas, not yet fully developed. He developed them just far enough, and just deep enough, to figure out orbital mathematics. But he left holes in his reasoning. Berkeley saw the holes and called Newton out on this. Subsequent theorists re-worked the foundations to render this branch of mathematics safe from Berkeleyan assaults.

That, as I say, is the usual story.

In 1987, a fellow named David Sherry wrote an article on the subject of Berkeley's critique of calculus, published in a journal called STUDIES IN THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. Sherry took a somewhat different view.  He puts this incident in the context of a pragmatic conception of what constitutes a "demonstration."

"In my view, many of Newton's demonstrations bring about understanding because they situate his results in a familiar context or rather an amalgamation of familiar contexts." Sherry objects to the notion that this was a bad thing, that it was a Newtonian defect that required Berkeleyan assistance.

Newton's demonstrations in particular, Sherry adds, "comprise representational techniques from kinematics, which would be familiar to anyone who grasped that subject. The purpose of Newton's demonstrations is to make plausible a particular manipulation of signs by showing that it is a natural consequence of representational techniques already employed."

The purpose, again, is understanding. Trying to make someone understand why a pitcher might in certain situations deliberately throw outside the strike zone in baseball. Only those who have some background in baseball and its vocabulary,  and likely who have played the game if only in a friend's back yard, could make sense of certain explanations, yet to people who meet that test, those demonstrations of the "intentional walk" would be perfectly cogent.

Berkeley simply didn't understand baseball well enough to understand the strategic value of an intentional walk -- he didn't understand kinematics well enough to grasp the idea of instantaneous velocity. "Baseball" in this analogy translates to such ideas as Oresme's diagrams, and Galileo's techniques in the discussion of momentum and speed.

Sherry's account seems a good deal less flattering to Berkeley than the standard view. His take on pragmatism in mathematics seems to suggest that 'foundations' are unnecessary so long as an existing practice exists. So the idea that Berkeley did something progressive by proving the inadequacy of the "foundations" of calculus falls by the wayside.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak