Skip to main content

A Few Words About Nietzsche II

Image result for superman flying

As promised, a more personal follow-up to the encyclopedia-derived material of yesterday.

It interests me because it relates, in an ambivalent way, to the controversy over "compatibilism."

Intuitively most people (but not most philosophers, or I would guess most neurologists) would say that a person can only be blamed for an action if she could have done otherwise.

So if there are no actions as to which one can accurately say that she could have done otherwise, she is not responsible for anything, there is no real distinction between actions per se and mere events. Given a thorough going determinism, then, conventional notions of moral responsibility, of perhaps of morality itself, go out the window.

That inference is, as I say, intuitively appealing but very controversial. Back on Feb. 9th I shared with you a recent survey of contemporary academic philosophers on this subject among many others. It indicated that a clear majority of those asked said that they are "compatibilists," that is, that they believe that notions of moral responsibility are compatible with determinism.

The incompatibilists, meanwhile, are split quite evenly between those who say, "yes, they are incompatible, we must reject one of them, so let's reject our notions of moral responsibility" and those who say the opposite, "yes, they are incompatible, so let's reject determinism."

What does Nietzsche say on this point? If I understand correctly, Nietzsche was an incompatibilist in one sense, a compatibilist in another. As I noted yesterday, Nietzsche sometimes uses "morality" in a pejorative sense, for what he is attacking. Sometimes, though, he uses it favorably, for the trans-valued system of values he is promoting. Determinism is a fact, he contended, and is inconsistent with moral responsibility, thus with morality in the pejorative sense. Hey hey, ho ho, MPS has got to go.  (Because I had to type that.)

The kind of morality that can and should survive after determinism sinks in is a morality without praise or blame, a responsibility-free sort. The "higher man," one who embraces this higher morality, will be good without crediting himself for goodness (it has been predetermined after all) and will separate himself from the herd without blaming the herd for the need for this separation.

Morality becomes a sort of aesthetic judgment after MPS goes, as it should.

That is Nietzsche's take. Or Stanford's take on Nietzsche's take, though it is worded so as to encourage the inference that some scholars of FN's works would disagree on some of these points.

And he would certainly have disdained the lame visual pun implied in the illustration I have employed for this post.

Comments

  1. I have not studied the philosophers' writings on this issue, and was not even aware of the terms "compatibilist" and "incompatibilist." Rather, I assumed that free will was, by definition, incompatible with determinism.

    I have given the subject of free will much thought, however, and have settled on my own belief. Let me describe it and then you can tell me where it fits in the compatibilism spectrum. I do not believe that free will exists, or even that the concept is coherent. If asked whether we want a vanilla or a chocolate ice cream cone, we can choose the one we want, but we cannot choose which one to want. Likewise with respect to moral choices: We can choose not to commit murder, but we cannot choose to want to not commit murder.

    One might conclude that, therefore, we have no moral responsibility. But we can and should assume that we do and impose punishments on people who commit murder. Even though we cannot choose to want to not commit murder, fear of punishment will become a factor in whether we want to commit murder, and therefore will affect our choice whether to commit murder.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak