Skip to main content

Congrats to Robert Audi

Image result for Robert Audi

Brian Leiter's blog informs me that the American Academy of Arts and Sciences recently elevated seven philosophers to the elite honor of membership in said Academy.

Sadly, I only recognized one of the seven names on the list. With all due respect to the other six (my ignorance is my problem, after all, not theirs), I will say a few words now about that one, Robert Audi, a professor at Notre Dame (go Irish). Not only does Audi teach philosophy there, he formerly held a chair in the Notre Dame Business School.

Audi, whose image you see here, has distinguished himself in epistemology as an advocate of fallibilistic foundationalism. He developed this view in response to the epistemic regress argument. What is all that? Glad you asked, dear reader.

We typically seek to defend and justify our beliefs by reference to other beliefs. I believe that the sun will rise in the east in the morning because I believe that the earth will continue to rotate in the same direction that it always has, over the next few hours. I believe THAT because ... etc.

But this creates "epistemic regress." Can all justified beliefs be justified by reference to other beliefs, or do some have to be go unjustified? There are, it seems, three possibilities -- we can and in principle must go on forever so there will be no unjustified beliefs; or we need not go on forever, so there are some "foundational" beliefs, the bottom turtle on which our belief systems rest; or we go on until we find that we've gone around in a circle, and we're justifying other beliefs by reference to our confidence that the sun will come up in the east, which was what we started off trying to justify.

This is a trilemma, and an argument for skepticism, because all of the possibilities seem bad ones: accepting the infinite regress amounts to accepting a lifetime of frustration chasing an ever receding hare; stopping at any foundation will seem arbitrary -- why that far and no further?; accepting the circle is perhaps the least appealing of all (though it has its champions).

Audi maintains that there are natural stopping points. Thus, his view is a foundationalism. But he also maintains that the foundations can be fallible. We don't have to demand that our foundations be necessary truths in order for them to serve us as foundations.

A detail in his argument for this proposition sticks to my mind. Audi writes somewhere about a trustworthy secretary for his faculty department who told him last Thursday that he has an appointment this Friday afternoon. Today, (Wednesday we will suppose), Audi is asked by a third party whether he is free Friday afternoon. He replies, "No, I'm not -- our department secretary told me last Friday that I have an appointment that day."

In this case, he has a true belief (that he is not free this Friday afternoon) based on a somewhat false memory (he is retrospectively misdating that conversation with the secretary.) This would seem to prove that valid inferences can flow from flawed premises, and that would seem in turn to support fallibilistic foundationalism.

Please don't critique that example under the impression you're critiquing Audi. IIRC, it's in a footnote of one of his books, and he would be aghast to have it invoked as paradigmatic of his philosophy. It is only paradigmatic of the skewed-yet-granular workings of MY memory.

I'll end here because, as Audi recognizes, one must end somewhere.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak