Skip to main content

The Idea of Civilian Casualties

Image result for siege engines

I've probably said this before but ... I'll go over it again to justify this neat drawing of a medieval siege engine.

it seems to me a key point in the political/military history of Europe in particular in the last several centuries that the whole issue of civilizing war by de-civilian-izing it.

The whole issue of who are the permissible victims of combat has turned around. In medieval times, the idea that attacking civilians was a bad thing would have seemed very odd. Attacking civilians was pretty much the key tactic of every army. Surrounding cities and starving them out was standard practice.
Indeed, in the high middle ages in Europe, attacking the other side’s army was something to be avoided if possible. You wanted to sneak around their army to get at their civilians. After all, their army was made up largely of noblemen, knights, who were worth a damned sight more than peasants and city rabble.
Only very slowly has the philosophy of war moved in the direction of seeing war as a slaughter that armies do TO EACH OTHER, and that they generally try to keep the civilians out of.
The reasons for this change are complicated and the newer view is not as obviously valid as we like to think.

General Sherman infamously took the war to the civilian population of the confederacy, avoiding contact with the grey uniforms where possible. He justified this on the ground that making war more obviously hell would mean ... fewer wars.

I would not go Sherman's route. Nor do I want to see a return to medievalism -- which has alas never completed its path out the door anyway. But I'm not sure the newer attitudes have finally got thinhgs right.

Suppose I embrace the premises, at least provisionally, that (1) wars between nation-states are going to continue for some time yet and (2) good people should try to make them a little less hellish, not more hellish, while they remain a fact of life, and (3) making them less hellish might mean having such institutions as the court in The Hague and punishing people for being "war criminals." Doing THAT means having a narrow definition of a war criminal so that it isn't just the label that is used to punishing prominent soldiers on the losing side of wars.

Even short of proceedings at The Hague, I suppose it is the case that anyone whom we would call a war criminal would be the lawful target of violence by the opposing side during that war.

Presuming all of that: do we have to say that war criminals have to be military? Even including the small number of civilians atop the chain of command that includes the military? What of someone who performs the role of a William Randolph Hearst in 1898. Promoting an aggressive war chiefly in order to sell some newspapers? Suppose the Spanish Empire had formed a covert unit to 'take him out.' Would the covert agents be war criminals because they were targeting a civilian? Or would he be the war criminal in a philosophically legitimate sense, making their mission a matter of a sovereign's self defense? (Abstracting again from the obvious fact that being on the winning side works like Clorox.) 

It seems to me that all the following propositions are reasonable: Hearst should reasonably be regarded as the criminal; he was a legitimate target in the course of a war which he did much to initiate; and the hypothetical agents would be soldiers not criminals. Thus, the military/civilian distinction is not an absolute one.


Comments

  1. Christopher,

    You're right that Sherman took the war to the civilian population, but he authorized his men only to take or destroy their property, and not to enter their homes. One would normally read "took the war to the civilian population" to include killing civilians, but that was not the case with Sherman.

    The greatest killing of civilians in war, which you don't mention, resulted from the bombing of London, Berlin, Hamburg, Dresden, Hiroshima, and Nagasaki in World War II.

    ReplyDelete
  2. We've got no quarrel on either point.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. That's too bad. I'll try to say something more controversial next time.

      Delete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak