Skip to main content

Moral Skepticisms (Really Just the One)


Some time ago, I don't know how long, I wrote in this blog about the book MORAL SKEPTICISMS by Walter Sinnott-Armstrong. After a long time away from that book I returned to it recently. Here is a summary.

Although the title, and the programmatic parts of the book, sound as if the plan was the emphasize the diversity of forms that moral skepticism might take, most of the book is devoted to a single argument, which may simply be resisted by moral cognitivists for different reasons. So the real debate is between moral skepticism singular and moral cognitivisms plural. 

Before I get to the argument, one critical semantic point. There is a distinction, among meta-ethical philosophers, between a normative proposition and a moral proposition. Some thinkers use "normative" as a broader term than "moral" and "normative but not moral" is a sort of intermediary thing between "is" statements and "ought" statements. So if we can't get from nature to morality directly, we may be able to do so indirectly by passing through amoral normativity. So runs a theory.

I'll leave aside how that is supposed to work for now. Here is an abbreviation of the key argument in the Sinnott-Armstrong book as one finds it at pages 74 to 77. 

1) If any person is ever justified in believing any moral claim, it must be by inference.
2) An inference must have either (a) no normative premises, or (b) some normative but no moral premises, or (c) some moral premises.
3) No person is ever justified in believing any moral claim by an inference with no normative premises.
4) No person is ever justified in believing any moral claim by an inference with some normative premises but no moral premises.
5) No person is ever justified in believing an inference to a moral claim from moral premises without a justification for believing that premise, itself a moral claim. 
6) Given both (1) and (5), any justification would have to consist in a chain of inferences with moral premises that would be either finite and circular, or infinite.
7) No person is ever justified in believing anything on the basis of a circular argument.
8) No person is ever justified in believing anything on the basis of an infinite chain of premises.
9) Thus, no person is ever justified in believing any moral claim. QED. 

The argument is formally tight. If justification requires one of a limited number of possibilities, and you have good reasons for eliminating each of those possibilities, then you have good reasons for believing that justification is not available. If you disagree with (9), you must disagree with something else along the way. And which one you baulk at tells us what sort of cognitivist you are. 

An intuitionist believes in non-inferential claims which serve as premises, and so rejects (1).
A moral naturalist will deny premise (3) -- perhaps the fact that certain things give humans pleasure is both a fact of nature and an anchor for moral reasoning. A normativist -- as I mentioned above -- will deny (4). A moral contextualist will deny (5). A moral coherentist will deny (7). And there are even -- odd as it sounds -- infinitists who deny (8).  

Accordingly, as Sinnott-Armstrong writes, even if we reject moral skepticism, its central argument serves the valuable purpose of classifying the possible non-skeptical views.  

My regular readers will by now surely recognize that I fit happily into the cognitivist-because-intuitionist camp. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak