Skip to main content

Bell Curves and Stock Prices


 
Last week our discussion took us as far as to a description of the normal or Bell curve.
See a depiction above. The numbers at the bottom of the graph refer to “standard deviations” from the norm.

We were discussing specifically mileage errors on maps. One standard deviation from the mean (the area between -1 and +1 on our graph above) accounts for roughly 68 percent of all the maps in our hypothetical database. Two standard deviations from the mean (the area between -2 and +2) account for roughly 95 percent of the maps. Three standard deviations account for 99 percent.

A normal curve for a phenomenon is taken as evidence of randomness. If there were some reason why the mapmakers of 17th century England were inclined to make a particular error that reason would show up as some non-normality in this chart. Perhaps the roads between these two places were especially good by the standard of the day, and the ease of travel created a general impression that the cities were closer than was/is the case. That might lead to a lop-sided (or as statisticians say a skewed) curve.
 
Or perhaps some famous troubadour of the day had sung of the “191 cursed miles” between his own home and that of his beloved. The song became quite popular and the right mileage number stuck in people’s heads.  This would make mistake less likely, and it would give the resulting curve a pointier look or (again to use the right jargon) a higher kurtosis than the above.
 
Now: it isn’t difficult to apply the same general idea of probability to the movement of the price of a stock. Consider every day in which XYZ’s stock has been listed on an exchange as a distinct datum. On any given day, the price has either risen, or fallen, or held its ground. As a first approximation, we might take a price that stays at the end of the day where it was at the start at the mid-point of our curve. As a first hypothesis, we might expect small upward moves and small downward moves to be about equally likely with each other, and slightly less likely than a flat day. Huge moves in either direction would be quite unlikely, some number of standard deviations away from the center.
 
If we create a chart for XYZ stock on these principles and it turns out not to look like a Bell curve, then could we fairly conclude that there is some unexpected joker in the deck? Is that how we might make our case that the Morgan Stanley downgrade had an impact? Because such reports create non-random distortions? Maybe the downgrade is acting something like our imaginary troubadour or like those atypically good roads that might once have distorted cartography.
 
Maybe. But we have to take account of other complications.
 
For example, there is a long-run upward trend in stock market prices, so that if we really tried to use no change as a mid-point for a particular stock’s prices, we’d risk a much skewed curve. The long-run trend is in some periods the result of inflation, in some periods the result of real underlying economic growth, and in some periods includes elements of both. Still, it exists, and some modification of our method is in order.
 
Suppose we compared a particular stock’s performance to that of a broader market (thus controlling for factors like price inflation and over-all economic growth). As a second approximation, then, we might say that a stock price that at the end of the day moves just as far, up or down, in percentage terms, as did the broader index on the same day (the Dow Jones, the S&P, the Nikkei, whatever) is at the midpoint of the curve. If we think that stock prices move randomly, we would expect days in which the stock of XYZ did a little better than the broader market, or a little worse, to be about equally likely with one another, and slightly less likely than a day on which XYZ does just what the broader market does. Huge departures from the broad market in either direction would be quite unlikely, some number of standard deviations from the center.   

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers