Skip to main content

The 'tautological' argument for faith



Last week I mentioned three philosophical arguments that concern very different subjects (and have very different advocates) but that have this in common: their critics think them tautological.

Under the prodding of a commenter, I'd like to be more specific about one of them today.

Some people argue that belief in God is necessary, and thus that God's existence must be postulated even if His existence cannot be proven, because He serves as the foundation of moral behavior. Let us call this argument FFM (faith for morals).

The critics say this is tautological. Does God tell us not to commit adultery because it is a bad thing, or is it bad because He tells us not to do it?  According to the critics of FFM, the FFM argument must say "both." Thus, it falls into circularity and tautology.

Now particular advocates of FFM might well have expressed themselves in ways that sound like this. But that isn't a very interesting inquiry. A much more important inquiry is: on a charitable reading can FFM as we've just described it avoid tautology?

This is an oft-popularized form of Kant's position. After all, Kant was committed to the proposition that the existence of God cannot be established through reason. Reason on his view ("pure reason") establishes analytic truths (in essence tautologies) and it establishes synthetic a prior truths also. BUT it only establishes the synthetic a priori to the extent that it limits itself to the phenomenal. That was the "critical" part of the critical philosophy.

Practical Reason
 
So ... assuming that God is really real, noumenal, the kind of reason that can tell us about Him is practical reason. In the popularized version of the argument I have in mind, that is translated into "faith."

An argument might proceed this way:

1. We'd have to start with some definition of morality that requires that moral agents do things either for good reasons or with good reasons. The preposition matters: but if our idea of morality requires that action occur for good reasons, we are basing morality on psychology. Right action is action from the right motive.

2. We might also develop the view -- a matter of moral epistemology if you please-- that a reason requires a firm foundation. Right action is action from the right motive, and the right motive must be one that will remain reliable over time.

3. What kind of thing could be a firm foundation for moral action? The advocate of FFM could proceed by process of elimination, and find that the various non-theistic reasons adduced are inadequately firm.

Codicil to 3. Kant himself developed an elaborate logical argument -- without reference to God -- for the categorical imperative as a foundation of morality. So perhaps such logical arguments can serve as  as the foundation of moral behavior. But in such works as Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone he writes as if this is not adequate. Presumably he means that ordinary folks who don't take doctoral courses at the best German universities won't grasp the categorical imperative as a logical argument.

4. An advocate of FFM might maintain that, to the extent that atheists act morally, they do so accidentally. Only theists [or very highly educated philosophical atheists?] who act morally can be relied upon to keep doing so.

5. Thus, there is a good non-cognitive reason for postulating the existence of a God who will reward us for right action.

Now: does this argument fall into the Euthyphro trap? Does it amount to saying that, say, adultery is wrong because God tells us not to do it and God tells us not to do it because it is wrong?

From the Elite

I submit that it does not. The argument has its weaknesses, and I have tipped off my view of some of them even while stating it. But it isn't a tautology.

Adultery, within a monogamous society, is simply a specific instance of a broader phenomenon: promise breaking. An individual who has committed to a monogamous relationship should stick with that for the same reasons people in general should keep promises: should remember that they rely on the promises others in society make to them all the time, and that it is impossible to treat the injunction "I'll break this promise" as a universal law.

God, as an omniscient Being, presumably can reason at least as well as a German professor of philosophy, and prohibits us from committing adultery because He knows we make promises to each other and rely upon them etc.

This isn't a tautology, although one might fairly see it as rather elitist. The gist of it is that the elite, who really understand why adultery is wrong, have a good non-cognitive reason for seeking to persuade the masses, who might not, that there is a God who has issued that command.  

Comments

  1. In my second comment to Christopher's April 14 post, I wrote "that it is irrelevant to Christopher's point that those who argue that God is necessary for morality also argue that his being necessary for morality requires us to postulate his existence." Christopher does not heed this in his new post, in which he writes, "Some people argue that belief in God is necessary, and thus that God's existence must be postulated even if His existence cannot be proven, because He serves as the foundation of moral behavior."

    If God is necessary for moral behavior, it does not follow that we must postulate His existence. We can instead conclude that moral behavior does not exist. But, you reply, we have empirical evidence that it does exist! Yes, and we have empirical evidence (which Christopher acknowledges in step 4) that atheists sometimes act morally. But only theists, step 4 adds, can be relied upon consistently to be moral. But this can empirically be shown to be false, as many theists are not consistently moral.

    I won't even address Christopher's bracketed comment that raises the possibility that very highly educated philosophical atheists can consistently be moral, as that would seem to destroy the theists' claim outright.

    ReplyDelete
  2. I'm sure that people who do believe in FFM will say (if they read this at all) that I've horribly misrepresented their ideas. You, Henry, seem to believe that I've conveyed it properly in all its non-tautological badnesses. And I'm content with that. Among its badnesses in the argument is the aspect of elitism that I highlighted in those brackets.

    There are those, I'm sure, who will argue with the contention that we have "empirical evidence that moral behavior exists." A follower of Skinner might say that the only sort of behavior that actually exists is the mechanical reaction to incentives and perpetuation of fixed habits. Calling any of this "moral" is arbitrary. Thus, invoking God as a foundation for moral behavior might (on that view) be a lot like involving faeries to explain the speed of unicorns.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Worth information for me... I really appreciate your effort..Thanks for sharing this on. Gap Analysis in UAE | Project Management in UAE

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers