Skip to main content

The Monty Hall Paradox

File:Monty hall abc tv.JPG


An old paradox, named after a game show host, the emcee of "Let's Make a Deal" continuously from 1963 to 1976, and intermittently as revived thereafter.

Monty Hall presented contestants with three curtains, often labeled A,B, and C, and asked them to make a choice. They would get whatever gift was behind the curtain they chose.

In the story/paradox, Monty tells you that behind one of the curtains is a magnificent new car, the car of your dreams. Behind the other two curtains, not-so-desirable gifts.

You tell him: "I pick A, Monty."

Monty: "Not so fast! I will now reveal what is behind curtain C."

The curtain opens, and there is some worthless gag gift, say a pile of shaving cream.

Monty: "Now, you can stay with your choice of A, or you can switch to B."

What should you do?

The usual first response, and for many people a very powerful intuitive response, is that it doesn't matter what you do. You now have just two curtains left, so the odds of being right either way are 1/2, right? So you can stay with A or go with B: it's all the same.

Another consideration: psychologically some people would probably be likely to stay with curtain A after the revelation as to C. After all, the revelation is consistent with your initial hypothesis. It may even be dignified with the word "evidence." So its evidence that you were right ... why change?

Well ... both of those responses are wrong. As a matter of simple game theoretical logic, the best thing to do is to switch -- go with curtain B now.

Why? Because Monty knows which curtain the prize is behind. The selection of C as the curtain to open was not random --he must have known the shaving cream was there. [If he didn't, he'd be at risk of selecting the curtain with the car behind it himself, ruining the whole bit.]  Since the selection of C wasn't random, it doesn't give you any new information.

Nor are your odds of being right 1 in 2. They were 1 in 3 when the game started and (because of the non-random nature of Monty's choice) they are still 1 in 3. As I say, there has been no new information.

The only rational thing to do is to switch to curtain B. There are now 2 chances in 3 that the car is there.

Its weirdly counter-intuitive, but perfectly logical. I love it so.  

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak