Skip to main content

Napoleon and Contingency




Just a quick book note today. The Simms book, EUROPE, is a very ambitious effort to put between two covers a discussion of the modern history (mostly the old-fashioned sort of history -- politics, war, and diplomacy) of the named continent.


The book gives to this convoluted subject matter, ranging from the fall of Constantinople in 1453 to headlines in the early 21st century, fewer than 700 pages. Excluding the lengthy source notes gives you just 530 pages.
Personally, I'm a sucker for Big Picture books like this.


Anyway: one of the themes of Simms' book is contingency. There was nothing inevitable, Simms tells us, "about the defeats of Charles V, Louis XIV, Napoleon, and Hitler."
Charles V was the King of Spain, and the Holy Roman Emperor, at the time when Spain was conquering much of the New World. Charles' big defeat was in his efforts in his Imperial capacity to suppress the Protestant Reformation. (He did keep it out of Spain, though!)
Louis XIV, France's Sun King, made his nation the dominant power in Europe (and a player of considerable importance in North America).  But he too suffered reversals. In the Treaty of Ryswick in 1697 he had to abandon French claims to Lorraine, and he had to give up his support for the Stuarts in England, recognizing William III as the lawful King there.


On the issue of contingency, though, I'd like to focus on the third of the above examples. where is the contingency in Bonaparte's defeat? Simms thinks it possible, had the winter of 1812-13 been less severe, that Napoleon could have cemented his military position deep inside Russia, including of course Moscow. If that had happened, it is further a possibility "that further setbacks might have sparked palace revolution against Alexander."


That is, after all, a lot like what happened in 1917. Czarist setbacks in a war against Germany were critical to the sparking of a revolution in Russia, and that allowed the Germans a separate peace on their eastern flank. [Yes, I know it didn't ultimately do the Kaiser any good. Still, that reflection makes the Napoleon counter-factual more intriguing.]


Let's turn this book note into an opportunity for philosophical reflection.


What exactly do we mean when we say that the bitterness of that weather in 1812-13 was a "contingency"?


We don't necessarily mean that it was a matter of chance in a cosmic sense, do we? That is, I could still believe that weather is a thoroughly deterministic system (if only all the pertinent facts were known) and still see Simms' point here.


What we mean, I submit, is that the weather in Russia that year was a matter outside the scope of what we usually call "history," the study of the development of human societies. The weather was exogenous to the history of 19th century Europe,not endogenous.


Simms is saying that European history, and we might hypothesize human history generally, is not a closed system. It is continuously receiving stimulus from without.


And that is a point worth making, if only because it excludes the theorizing of a Spengler or Toynbee, who seem to require that history have its own laws, its own endogenous chains of cause and effect.

Comments

  1. Christopher,

    I have not read Spengler or Toynbee, but I find it difficult to believe that they were unaware that the weather and other exogenous factors affect history. Their differences with other historians on this question must have been more subtle than that. If you can't explain this in a quick reply, perhaps you could devote a post to it.

    Also, I do not see a bright line between exogenous and endogenous factors. If John Wilkes Booth's bullet hadn't killed Lincoln, then Reconstruction might have turned out differently. Suppose his bullet hadn't killed Lincoln because a clap of thunder startled him and his bullet entered Lincoln's shoulder, non-fatally, instead of his head. Had he been a better gunman, however, he might have still killed Lincoln. Or suppose the gun failed to fire. This might have occurred solely by chance, because it was in the nature of guns at the time to fail to fire a certain percentage of the time. Or Booth might not have been adequately cleaning his gun, and we cannot know which explanation accounts for the gun's failure to fire.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak