Skip to main content

Thoughts About Risk Aversion

New100front.jpg


Risk aversion is a straightforward name for the psychological fact that humans are often willing to pay a premium for certainly, or at least for limiting the zone of uncertainty.


Suppose you, dear reader, appear on a television game show. The master of ceremonies says to you,
"I can give you a nice crisp $100 bill right now!"


You say, "oh, goodie."


"Or!" he continues with a dramatic flourish, "I can flip a coin. If the coin comes up tails, you'll get nothing. If the coin comes up heads, you'll get $200."


Let us suppose there is no element of what finance types call "counter-party risk" here. Your counter-party is the emcee. We'll assume he is entirely trustworthy and that there is nothing tricky about the coin flip itself.


The expected value of the coin flip, in simple arithmetical terms, is ($200 + 0) ÷ 2 = $100. The value of the payoff if you reject the coin flip is, again, $100. So you should on one quite abstract level be indifferent which course the emcee takes. You might even want to flip a coin to decide whether to tell him to flip the coin.


Except that you won't. Unless you are an extraordinary specimen you, dear reader, will be risk averse. One of the choices involves just taking what has been offered you, the other involves the risk that you'll end up with nothing. You'll opt for the former.


Let me stop there. If any of my readers is NOT risk averse in the sense I've just described, let me hear from you in the comments.

Comments

  1. One's decision whether to take the $100 or risk it for $200 may depend upon a factor that you have not considered: how badly one needs the $100. If I am starving and the $100 will enable me to eat, I'll take it. If I would use the $100 to purchase a luxury item, then I might as well risk it in the hope of being able to buy a $200 luxury item.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Henry,

    Good point. Even to a poor person, though, this point seems at first blush to cut both ways. It means that losing the chance to lock in the first $100 would be that much more devastating, but it also means getting the $200 would be a more tempting boon.

    If we think of the utility of money as a curve we can resolve this (the way you suggest). To someone who has nothing, $100 is extremely important. The likelihood of a second chunk of money of the same nominal value will also be important, but maybe a smidge less so.

    Bill Gates, meanwhile, is at or near the top of a concave curve. Another $100 will mean literally nothing -- the line is horizontal. Conceivably the curve has headed down, so another $100 is just a burden to Gates, a little extra weight he'd be expected to carry about in his wallet until he got it home and could safely use it to tip the butler or something. "Whew! what a relief to have that off of me! I wish I had bet on the next coin flip and lost!"

    A similar point is often made through a slightly more complicated thought experiment known as the St Petersburg paradox, because of its origins in a pre-Napoleonic era in Russian history when St Pete was a gambling mecca.

    I'll link you to a discussion of that.

    http://www.econport.org/content/handbook/decisions-uncertainty/basic/paradox.html

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak