Skip to main content

Continuing the thought on Chesterton

Image result for Chesterton


So: what was Chesterton really saying when he wrote this?

"Since the modern world began in the sixteenth century, nobody's system of philosophy has really corresponded to everybody's sense of reality: to what, if left to themselves, common men would call common sense. Each started with a paradox; a peculiar point of view demanding the sacrifice of what they would call a sane point of view. That is the one thing common to Hobbes and Hegel, to Kant and Bergson, to Berkeley and William James. A man had to believe something that no normal man would believe, if it were suddenly propounded to his simplicity: as that law is above right, or right is outside reason, or things are only as we think them, or everything is relative to a reality that is not there. The modern philosopher claims, like a sort of confidence man, that if once we will grant him this, the rest will be easy: he will straighten out the world, if once he is allowed to give this one twist to the mind."

On Sunday March 22d I gave my reasons for believing that much is left unsaid here. The gist of those reasons in shorter form is as follows:

1) This can't really be a 16th century calamity if the earliest possible example is Thomas Hobbes, a man who did no philosophizing at all until well into the 17th century.

2) The supposed calamity is metaphysical in nature, whereas the representative thought attributed to Hobbes is political. So on a little scrutiny, the earliest real example Chesterton offers is Berkeley, who starts writing in the second half of the 18th century. Why, again, the specificity about the silent 16th?

3) My best guess is that the phrase "right is outside reason" is meant to reference Kant, and the turn of the 18th into the 19th century. But it seems an off description, as if Chesterton is punning on the word "right" and winking at us. What is going on?

What happened in the 16th century that may be at the back of GKC's mind? The Protestant Reformation, surely. His underlying line of thought is that the Reformation was wrong, and the cause of all wrongness that has come after. He doesn't simply want to say, "various bad thoughts have been thought since the 16th century, so the Reformation was bad." That would sound naive and, frankly, ignorant. He wants to hint at that same contention while sounding sophisticated and erudite.

But the underlying thought is the naive and ignorant one.

Comments

  1. Christopher,

    Please explain #3. How is "right is outside reason" a reference to Kant, and what is the pun on "right"?

    ReplyDelete
  2. Henry, As I understand Kantian epistemology, "reason" forms the phenomenal world and helps us to understand the same. Reason can't inform us as to the noumenal world, which is more real than the phenomenal. So "right" (in a descriptive sense, the ability to be right about the really real) is outside [the capabilities of] reason.

    I believe Chesterton is making a reference to this, both mentioning Kant in his list of names then using this phrase "right is outside reason" in his list of examples of non-sensical ideas.

    BUT if he is doing so there is a bit of punning involved. For Kantian ethics doesn't put right [in a moral sense] outside reason at all. Kantian ethics is a rigorous effort to derive right via the use of reason. Furthermore, since this phrase comes immediately after the precis of Hobbesian thought, "law is above right," the passage uses the ambiguity in the term "right" to slide from political/ethical concerns into the epistemological/metaphysical field.

    See my March 23d post for a fuller exegesis.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak