Skip to main content

Continuing a discussion of the Supreme Court's term

Authority of Law by James Earle Frasier

So now for the two Big Ones.

1) The Supreme Court's third big Obamacare case came down this June.

The Court's response to the first Obamacare challenge, you will remember, the NFIB decision of 2012, upheld the health-insurance mandate against the charge that it did not come within any one of the federal government's "enumerated" powers under the constitution. The decision, in the law's favor, held that it didn't come within the meaning of "commerce among the states" but that this doesn't matter all that much because it did come within the meaning of the taxing power. This vote came down 5 to 4.

The second challenge involved religious objections to the provision of certain types of health insurance. The opponents of the law won that one at the high court, 5 to 4, carving out a religion-based exception to the scope of the employer mandate. The winning bloc of five consisted of Justices Alito, Roberts, Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas. This left Ginsberg, Breyer, Kagan, and Sotomayor in dissent. Personally, my expectation going into June 2015 was that the same five-Justice bloc would hold together to take another swipe at the over-all scheme via the issue of statutory interpretation raised in  the third challenge, King v. Burwell. 

I was wrong. The The court voted 6 to 3 to uphold the over-all statutory scheme, even though that required a generous reading of some poorly drafted language. The winning bloc this time consisted of Justices Roberts, Kennedy, Ginsburg, Breyer, Sotomayor, and Kagan. Last years' dissenters plus the Chief Justice and Kennedy.

The opinion was a much more sweeping affirmation of the statutory scheme than was necessary to get to that result. The court could have used Chevron reasoning, after all - it could simply have said, "in such matters of statutory construction, we defer to the administrative expertise of the relevant executive officials." That would have left the scheme in place, but would have left it subject to being overturned if the Republicans win the next election and the partisan loyalties of the relevant administration officials change. But it didn't.

Something else the majority could have done, but didn't, was invoke federalism arguments. This would have given a conservative slant to the decision, saying "a literal construction of the disputed phrase would leave the federal government too demanding vis-a-vis the states, so our duty to the federal-state balance is to avoid such a reading." Some observers expected such reasoning, based on observations that Justice Kennedy made during oral argument.

Kennedy told the attorneys for the law's opponents during argument that if their interpretation of the law prevailed, "the states are being told either create your own exchange, or we'll send your insurance market into a death spiral." Dahlia Litwick of Slate called this the "most important moment" from the arguments. It's less important-seeming now. Kennedy didn't write for the majority, nor did he write a concurrence (as of course he could have had the federalism angle been important to him), nor did Roberts' opinion for the court give that argument more than a brief passing glance.

Why not? I'm not sure. But the bottom line is that Roberts' decision gives the administration an uncomplicated victory as to what the statute means, without dragging either federalism or administrative discretion in to it.

2) Gay Marriage and the 14th amendment

Even bigger, Obergefell v. Hodges. Justice Kennedy, writing for the majority (no concurrences, four dissents), found that prohibitions on the marriage of same sex couples violate the fourteenth amendment, apparently as a consequence of the "synergy" between the equal protection clause and the substantive reading of the due process clause.

I won't try to find something new to say about this case. I will only say that Kennedy is a bit too sparse for my taste in his discussion of doctrinal matters. For example, especially on the equal protection side of the synergy, readers will naturally want to know what is the level of scrutiny that is supposed to attach to laws that discriminate between homosexuals and heterosexuals.  Strict? intermediate? mere rationality?

I think Kennedy is trying to say that the laws in question fail even at the lower tier, they are simply irrational. So he doesn't need to inquire which level is the right one. That either indicates that the whole conceptual apparatus of tiered scrutiny has outlasted its usefulness and Justices will feel free hereafter just to ignore it, OR it is simply sloppy. I would welcome the former but suspect the reality is the latter.

The phrase that comes to mind, the phrase often used to define when strict scrutiny is called for, is "discrete and insular minority." I'm not sure how discrete homosexuals are as a group. They surely are not insular. Thus on one traditional way of looking at the problem, discrimination against them is not subject to strict scrutiny. Still, it seems that the case is strong (leaving the liberty clause aside) that such discrimination should be subject to the intermediate level, the same level that applies to discrimination against women for example. And that it should fail of such scrutiny. If the three-tiers stuff is going to survive at all, it would have been good for the court to be clear about the fact that it does survive, and the place of this particular fact pattern therein.

That concludes my summary of five decisions of this term. But there is more to be said about this term, that escapes an opinion-by-opinion review, and I will say some more about it in my next post, Thursday.


Comments

  1. This comment has been removed by the author.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Marty Lederman observes that the dissenters in Obergefell say virtually nothing in defense of state justifications for banning gay marriage, and that is because there are no legitimate ones. The true reasons for the ban: "moral disapproval, biblical injunction, anxiety about homosexuality, and occasionally even animus--are unavailable to the states as legitimate justifications; and therefore it's understandable that those justifications--the actual grounds for state discrimination--do not even make an appearance in the Obergefell opinions."
    http://balkin.blogspot.com/2015/07/the-remarkable-disappearance-of-state.html

    ReplyDelete
  3. This comment has been removed by a blog administrator.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak