Skip to main content

Planned Obsolescence

Image result for desoto

When I was young, there was a lot of talk about "planned obsolescence," especially in the automotive industry.

The idea was that the Detroit Big Three (who dominated the auto manufacturing world in those distant days) were deliberately creating cars that would wear out in four to five years and need to be replaced. This was understood to be both rational and predatory behavior, a sign of how buyers and sellers are necessarily at odds. Because how could makers not want repeat business? And how could motorists not want long lasting vehicles?

Nobody uses that expression any more today. Perhaps the theory now seems somewhat silly. The duration of cars has significantly expanded since the days when that expression was a thing. And the Cubans have demonstrated throughout the Castro era that it is perfectly possible to keep even 1950s era Detroit vehicles on the road in working condition into the second decade of the 21st century. How? Did the "planning" go wrong, or was it never directed as the cliche implied in the first place?

The underlying idea seems to involve hidden assumptions about interest rates.   Suppose I make a product (just call it an 'x') that lasts three years. Smith, my actual or potential competitor, has a design on the drawing board for a product that will do everything my x does, but will do it for six years.  The implication of the cliche is that t I approach him and say, "Don't ruin a good thing. Why don't you keep your product life down to three years, and we'll both get return business?"

But he has prepared to sell something that will be valued by the public more highly than what I am selling. The market could very well have room for both of us; the low-priced x and its higher priced but longer-lasting cousin. It isn't obvious my proposal would be riveting to him.

Now, you object, he'd have to charge a much higher price than mine, since his revenue is in effect going to have to last him twice as long product-for-product. Wouldn't that higher price have to be twice as high?

No. Just as an arithmetical matter, his income stream will be at parity with mine so long as the premium he charges is enough for him to buy bonds with it, such that the income from those bonds plus the principal he's already earned will add up to the price of that second x, the one he is not going to be selling at the start of year 4.  Of course he'll want low-risk bonds for this purpose.

My conclusion: planned obsolescence is a theoretical possibility that becomes more likely the longer interest rates are kept low by central bankers, for in that environment the longer-lived products may become less likely to pay for themselves.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers