Skip to main content

William James and Mind-Body Neutrality II

Image result for coffee temperature paradox

In yesterday's post I laid out three "neutralist" theories and said something about the relationship of William James' thought to each. I'd like to tie that line of inquiry up a bit today.

Again, the theories are: neutral monism; dual aspect theory; panpsychism.

What they maintain in each case is that there is some stuff that is neither mental nor physical, and that the mental and physical realms are constructions out of this stuff, so that we can allow for mind-body interaction without freaking out over HOW?

For a neutral monist, the stuff is an underlying collection of data or unclassified facts such as an image of a piece of paper.

For a dual aspect theory, the stuff is God, the Universe, Everything Considered as a Totality.

For a panpsychist, the stuff is, well, mindful matter. Which includes all matter (and, likely enough, all mind.)

I shared yesterday, too, my own impression that the first listed of those three arises out of a principle of parsimony, the Ockhamist impulse to build the world out of the fewest components. The third of those arises rather out of metaphysical exuberance, gleefully dispensing with parsimony. The middle term, Monism, may be considered middle in precisely this regard.

This brings us to the paradox we might face if we study James' texts with this typology in mind. We seem to see a close resemblance between views A, B, and C, which escaped him. Moreover, he discussed both A and C, both favorably though without decisive adoption as his own view, Yet his discussions of A seem to take place in a different compartment of his mind (or body!) from his discussions of C. They don't come in contact,

Moreover, he had a visceral opposition to B. It was "the Absolute" -- the "upper dogmatism,"

So: what is going on here?

Perhaps we should regard the plausibility of neutralist theories of mind and body as akin to the temperature of coffee. One can like hot coffee (in certain contexts), like iced coffee as well (in other contexts) yet reject and disdain lukewarm coffee.

James' philosophy was in large part an effort to prove that human deliberations matter. "To think is the only moral act." Our deliberations are not forced or predetermined, and the actions into which they issue can change our lives and the lives of others around us in which for which there is no limit. We can get to that self-conception either by heating up the coffee or by cooling it down, James suspected, and he was willing to entertain either approach.

The lukewarm coffee? Despite its family resemblance to the good stuff(s), it wouldn't get the job done, and the only way to pretend that it did, was to go over to the other side.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak