Skip to main content

Descartes' Innatism

Image result for rene descartes images


I'm working my way carefully through Fiona Cowie's book, WHAT'S WITHIN? NATIVISM RECONSIDERED (1999), a book I've only skimmed until now. I believe I've mentioned it here a time or two on the basis of the skimming and its reviews.

The book, which began life as a doctoral dissertation, is a look at Fodor and Chomsky in particular, and their revival of elements of classical rationalism, especially with regard to a priori ideas.

Today I'll focus on an early point, within Cowie's historical discussion. She asks: what exactly was the classical debate, the one featuring Descartes and Leibniz on one side, figures such as Hobbes and Locke on the other, really about?  It is not easy to pin in down. The empiricists sometimes wrote as if the rationalists were saying that a baby comes into the world already knowing, say, what a triangle is, or what constitutes a prime number. Babies clearly don't. And the old rationalists denied this is what they meant.

Descartes wrote that he and others on his side of the dispute "simply mean that we have within ourselves the faculty of summoning up the idea" of a triangle, a prime, or a Perfect Being.

On the other hand Locke etc. weren't denying the tautology that we are capable of summoning up the ideas that we really have.  We were then born with the possibility of knowing whatever we later came to know. That even stubborn Anglophones don't deny. Is that all the "faculty" within means?

Cowie argues for what she calls a "special faculties" interpretation of the dispute. What Descartes meant was that the acquisition of some of our ideas, particularly our geometrical ideas, were due to the activation of certain features in our minds. As is well known, he thought of "mind" in an intangible sense here, he wouldn't have said, "certain wiring configurations in the brain." Still, he saw the mind as divided into units, some with quite special/limited purposes. The modularity of the mind was critical to what he meant by innateness.

In his COMMENTS OF A CERTAIN BROADSHEET, Descartes makes what Cowie takes to be a revealing analogy. "This is the same sense as that in which we say that ... certain diseases such as gout or stones are innate" in certain families. People with a genetic disposition may have the faculty of contracting gout. This doesn't mean that they have gout as infants. Nor does it simply mean that gout is a possibility for humans. It means that there is a specific gout contracting ability -- that which as we in   the 21st century would say is passed along by the genes of the families Descartes had in mind. The possession of this faculty makes it neither more nor less likely that the possessor will someday get the bubonic plague, or the flu.

So what Locke was really objecting to, when he objected to innatism, was the compartmentalization of the mind. He believed that "what's within" is a quite general learning capacity. When he spoke of the blank slate of our mind at birth we are to understand the singularity of that image as critical to it. It is all ONE slate, and the same chalk that writes geometrical demonstrations there is the chalk that generalizes about the behavior of squirrels, or contemplates whether there must be a First Mover. There is a learning faculty in the human mind, so to speak, there is no congeries of special faculties.

I find this a helpful clarification as to what that debate was about.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak