Skip to main content

The Prisoner's Dilemma and Pragmatism



Image result for prisoners dilemma

Let's state The Prisoner’s Dilemma explicitly. Just 'cause I'm in a mood.

Suppose two criminals have together robbed a bank. Police have captured and are
interrogating them both. The police could get them both on a lesser charge (say, reckless
discharge of their weapons) even if neither confesses on the big charge (the armed robbery).


They are interrogating the prisoners in separate facilities, thus with no chance to communicate.


The police offer each prisoner, simultaneously, the following deal:


“Confess, ratting on your buddy, and you will be set free. We will convict your buddy and he will
serve three years in prison. If you refuse to confess, your buddy may well take this same deal,
and you will serve three years in prison, he will walk free.


“If you rat on him and he rats on you, we’ll have to convict and punish both of you.But we won’t w
ant your cooperation to go unrewarded, so in that case we promise a one-year cut on your
sentence, from 3 years down to 2. We’re also offering that as part of your buddy’s deal, too.


“Oh, and by the way, if nobody talks, then nobody will get the three year sentence, but BOTH of
you will get  one year on reckless discharge -- we don’t need any confession for that.”


So in shortened form:


Both talk: each gets two years.


Only one talks, that one goes free, the other gets three years.


Nobody talks, each gets one year.

As graphed above.


What is fascinating about this from the point of view of game theorists and social philosophers is
that purely rational self-interest, pursued by each prisoner/player, leads to a worse result for both
than less rational seeming solidarity (and silence).


It is in the rational interest of each player to talk to the police. Why? Because whatever the “other”
fellow does, confessing gets “me” the best result. If  Other talks it is better for Me to have talked
than not to have talked (two years rather than three). If on the other hand Other stays silent, it is
again better for Me to have talked than not to have talked (walking free is better than doing one
year). Other must EITHER  talk OR stay silent, so that exhausts the possibilities, and in both
cases, I am better off if I have talked.


But … it is better for both of us if both of us refuse to do that rational self-interested calculation,
and simply refuse to talk. After all, if both prisoners follow the reasoning above, each talks, and
they each do two years. If both stay silent, each does just one year.

Silence is better pragmatically, although talking ‘should’ be better from the point of view of
individual self-interested rationality. Thus, pragmatic consequences prove the  vulnerability
individual self-interested rationality.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak