Skip to main content

What is Science?



Image result for Marie Curie


What we nowadays call science is a specific practice that developed within a specific time and place,
that is, within, Europe beginning around 1500, that is, during Columbus's voyages. This was also,
I believe, around the time when a Polish fellow whose Latin name was Copernicus was taking up
in a serious way the study of astronomy, where he would in time make a name for himself.

So: what was this new thing? Any formulation draws debate. Sticking to a very abstract level, I think
one can say that science is a self-corrective process in which hypotheses are developed and
refined so that they can suggest experiment. (In the case of astronomy, since we can't haul planets
into a laboratory, 'experiment' has generally meant targeted observation.)

These experiments can then falsify some hypotheses, uphold others, and demand the refinement of
still others. Scientific peers seek to confirm each other’s results and build on each other's findings,
in a way that cumulatively builds an ever more accurate picture of the natural world and how humans
can successfully live within it.

This is as I've said, a quite abstract statement. It is also idealizing. When I describe science in such
terms, I make it out to be not just an Idea, but an ideal. Indeed, one worth dying for.

The black-and-white photo above is of Marie Curie, who embodied this ideal. Even the law
that energy can be neither created nor destroyed, one that seemed very well-founded (and indeed WAS
well-founded) before she took up her work on radium, soon came to be seen as in need of important
modification. The prestige of science has been earned the hard way. Curie died of aplastic anemia, that is,
of radiation poisoning.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak