Skip to main content

Spinozism in Six Points

Image result for star of David

Just to practice concision.

1) In anthropology, Spinoza emphasized what we are not. We are not a "kingdom within the kingdom." We are a subject of nature, which is the only kingdom.

2) In metaphysics, Spinoza is remembered for his naturalized God, or for his deification of nature. They work out to be the same thing, which is the point. This has the odd-seeming but predictable consequence that he has been called an atheist by some commentators and a "God-intoxicated man" by others.

3. In epistemology, Spinoza believed in "geometrical order." The best way to approach truth was to start with a small number of premises that are recommended by their clarity and the difficulty of seeing how things could be otherwise, and to spin out their logical consequences.

4. In ethics, Spinoza believed that the real problem was the confusion and frustration that comes our way when we think we ARE a kingdom with the kingdom, and the solution is just to learn better.

5. In politics, Spinoza asserted that "the validity of an agreement rests on its utility, without which the agreement automatically becomes null and void,” by which dictum he meant to undermine 'social contract' theorizing.

6. Finally, Spinoza is associated with a variety of Biblical exegesis which presumes that the Bible offers only a moral system -- it does not teach philosophical or scientific truths.

Comments

  1. Christopher, if I may clarify your second point for those who have not studied Spinoza, by "naturalized God" you don't mean that God is part of nature (that is, a material object), but that he is nature. Thus, Spinoza was a pantheist.

    Your fourth point requires elaboration if it is to have meaning, at least to me.

    Your fifth point caused me to wonder who theorized about social contract before Spinoza; the first social contract theorist I know of was Locke, but I didn't know whether he lived before Spinoza. It turns out that they were both born in 1632. But Locke outlived Spinoza by 27 years, and I don't know whether he wrote about the social contract while Spinoza was alive.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. I made a mistake. Hobbes was a social contract theorist who was born in 1588--42 years before Locke and Spinoza. But he outlived Spinoza by almost three years.

      Delete
    2. I meant 44 years before Locke and Spinoza. I wish that your blog permitted editing.

      Delete
  2. Henry,

    With regard to the fourth point: I'm thinking especially of Spinoza's elaborate definitions of the emotions, and especially of love as "joy, accompanied by an idea of its external cause." The point, for him, is that since the source of our joy is external, it is (usually) insecure, and we set ourselves up for misery trying to make the things we love last as long as we do, or trying to bind the people we love to us in ways that set us up for jealousy and other miseries. Ethics, for Spinoza, means abandoning all loves except the love of God, or nature, and understanding that THAT love means the joyful acceptance of what comes.

    And yes, Spinoza's comments on the social contract had Hobbes as their target. LEVIATHAN appeared in 1651, when Spinoza was in his late teens.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Thank you; that clarifies it well. But, in #4, I think that "with" should be "within," which would conform to the quotation in #1. A "kingdom," I take it, means nature or God, or having the power of nature or God.

      Delete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak