Skip to main content

ON WHAT MATTERS

The two books with the first volume's cover showing


Derek Parfit's book, ON WHAT MATTERS, published in two volumes in 2011, acquired a third volume from his posthumous writings, in 2017 (he died on the very first day of that year).

The book was much anticipated, generating both discussion groups and an academic conference in advance of its 2011 publication.

Parfit's thesis, in short, is that there are three distinct moral theories and that, if each is pursued rigorously, it ends up in concord with the other two. Kantian deontology, utilitarianism, and contractualism are all different paths on different slopes of the same mountain. They lead to the same behavior: that is, the paths come together at the summit.

That's a bold claim. Decoded (in accord with pragmatism) it means that the differences turn out to be merely conceptual not practical. A right-thinking Kantian and a right-thinking proponent of either of the other views will do the same thing at the notorious trolley switch.

Today I will merely say a few words about the "contractualist" path up the alleged mountain. The inclusion of this path on the metaphorical mountain will sound odd to some readers. These days if philosophers set up a deontology/consequentialist contrast, the "third way" they usually include would be Aristotelian "virtue ethics." There is none of that for Parfit. The third way for him is contractualism.

Also (related), ethicists tend to regard the "contractualist" approach to their field as specialized: it is a theory about the bases of social institutions, the state, and revolution. It is not a theory of ethics as such.

For Parfit, however, contractualism is the third way up the mountain. Scanlon, in a 1998 book, WHAT WE OWE TO EACH OTHER, paved the way for him here, generalizing social contract theory into contract theory, sans adjective.

It isn't all that surprising to think of Scanlon meeting Kant at the top of the mountain. Scanlon had some indebtedness to Kant even at the bottom of the mountain.

There is an important difference though. At least Scanlon thinks it an important difference, Parfit evidently not. Scanlon, thinking through what we owe each other according to a hypothetical contract, says that "an act is wrong if its performance under the circumstances would be disallowed by any set of principles for the general regulation of behavior that no one could reasonably reject  as a basis for informed, unforced, general agreement." 

That is a complicated statement and I won't try to parse it now. But the gist seems to be that if I believe Sam (a stranger, with whom I have no real-world contractual relation) did some wrong to me, I am asserting that his action would be disallowed by any principles we could reasonably have imagined entering into if we had not been strangers.

What does this have to do with Kant? Scanlon is talking of real people, in particular social circumstances, who know their own lives. I have my life, the stranger has his, and the two collide in some way. I am expected to prove that a self-justifiable explanation he offers me is irrational, that "reasonable" people must "reject". This might involve a much more concrete inquiry than Kant has in mind, one much more focused on circumstances. More phenomenal, less noumenal.

To be more clear, bring John Rawls into the picture. Rawls posited a "veil of ignorance" in the contracting position. Scanlon posits none The people engaged in the hypothetical reasoning he has in mind know who they are. If Rawls is getting Kant right, then Scanlon would seem to be importantly different from Kant.

But I'll stop trying to sort it all out.  Certainly my formation of my own views on ethical and meta-ethical matters are utterly independent of such historical byways as whether Rawls is or is not getting Kant right. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a maj...

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak...

Recent Controversies Involving Nassim Taleb, Part I

I've written about Nassim Taleb on earlier occasions in this blog. I'll let you do the search yourself, dear reader, for the full background. The short answer to the question "who is Taleb?" is this: he is a 57 year old man born in Lebanon, educated in France, who has been both a hedge fund manager and a derivatives trader. He retired from active participation from the financial world sometime between 2004 and 2006, and has been a full-time writer and provocateur ever since. Taleb's writings for the general public began where one might expect -- in the field where he had made his money -- and he explained certain financial issues to a broad audiences in a very dramatic non-technical way. Since then, he has widened has fields of study, writing about just about everything, applying the intellectual tools he honed in that earlier work. As you might have gather from the above, I respect Taleb, though I have sometimes been critical of him when my own writing ab...