I mentioned Whitehead's apparent sympathy with Heraclitus in my last post about him. My reading had not yet at that point discovered Process and Reality. Part II, Chapter Ten, which takes the form of an extended meditation on the sentiment "all things flow." In Heraclitus' Greek, panta rhei.
The sympathy is here made explicit. Indeed, a full understanding of that sentiment is said to be one of the main goals of philosophizing at all.
Some of the thinkers of the early modern world tried to ban flow, or fluency, from their picture of the world.
But Whitehead adds, "Newton, that Napoleon of of the world of thought, brusquely ordered fluency back into the world, regimented into his 'absolute, mathematical time, flowing equably without regard to anything external.' He also gave it a mathematical uniform in the shape of his Theory of Fluxions."
What a marvelous packing of two concise sentences! Almost as magnificent as Heraclitus' two words.
"Newton, a Napoleon of the world of thought," from a Brit writing less than six score years after Napoleons final defeat by the Brits, this phrase is itself rich. It involves an acknowledgement of genius, but one that is at least a touch grudging. The subsequent language, of a brusque order, regimentation, the dispensing of uniforms, enhances the idea of Newton as a conqueror, in a world in which not few who are conquered are grateful.
Let us fill out the metaphor a bit. Think of the medieval scholastic ideas of time as the Bourbon regime. Think, then, of Descartes -- and even more so of Spinoza -- as Danton, Robespierre and the other revolutionaries, proud of their break with the past and willing to do without the monarch of flux altogether. Newton is then the Napoleon indeed. The monarchy of time returns, uniformed with the new mathematics of what we call calculus and what Newton called fluxions.
Yet Napoleon came to a bad end, confined to a remote volcanic island with no scope for his military genius or political ambition. Whitehead was well aware of early 20th century physics. He knew that Einstein had proved to be the Duke of Wellington of the world of thought.
Indeed, Whitehead may have fancied himself the Talleyrand, negotiating the post-Newtonian world with the other philosophers at the Congress of Vienna of the world of thought.
As to the fluidity of the cosmos, Whitehead's view is that it is of two sorts: the pursuit by many actual occasions/societies (mindfully or otherwise) of their own ideals on the one hand, and the perpetual perishing of all, regardless of ideas, on the other hand. He calls these the fluidity of creativity and of transition, respectively. He finds references to this distinction in the works of Locke, but regrets that Locke did not put "his scattered ideas" on the subject of time together in a systemic way.
just a linguistic or semantic remark on this piece. IMHO, flow pairs better with fluidity than with fluency. I understand people have interests, motives and preferences vis-a-vis expression and language. And, I admit ignorance when it comes to Whitehead's linguistic style and preferred expression(s). Language is fluid, in parallel with preferences. So, no, I am not the most articulate squid in the aquarium. But, I do love a good read. ANW sounds like a metaphysician.
ReplyDeleteAm good with that.
This comment has been removed by the author.
DeleteWhitehead began his adult life as a philosopher of mathematics. He was the co-author (with Bertrand Russell) of one of the defining works in that field, PRINCIPIA MATHEMATICA (final volume pub. 1913). They argued in three volumes that the idea of a number is in principle reducible to the idea of a set of sets. This "logicism" remains one of the handful of fundamental positions in that branch of philosophy. It is fascinating to me the different paths that Russell and Whitehead then took in their subsequent development.
DeleteThis comment has been removed by the author.
ReplyDeleteIt should be said that there are (to my mind, odd) passages in PROCESS AND REALITY in which Whitehead seems to be intent on reminding us of his earlier days toiling on sets and numbers. Part IV, Chapter II, "The Theory of Extension" starts off with Venn diagrams and seems to be devoted to an axiomization of ... something or other. Example, "If there be one, and only one, intersection of two regions, A and B, those regions are said to overlap with 'unique intersection'; if there be more than one intersect, they are said to overlap with 'multiple intersections.'" I'm afraid I've mostly skimmed those bits.
ReplyDelete