Skip to main content

The Static Universe, Part II

As I indicated in yesterday's post, I was disappointed by Ratcliffe's book, The Static Universe: exploding the myth of cosmic expansion (2010).



He fails to make his case, even to a will-to-believer like me, and he mixes up his case with a polemic against all of modern geometry, going back as far as Carl Friedrich Gauss. [Gauss is the rightwardmost figure in the photo above, a still of the afterlife of great mathematicians as represented in the stage show Fermat's Last Tango.]


The wrongness of the paths followed by modern cosmology, then, has its origin prior to the mid-point of the 19th century, when Gauss started working on non-Euclidean space.

As some of my readers may have learned at school, Euclid's geometry rests in large part upon the following axiom: "If a line segment intersects two straight lines forming two interior angles on the same side that sum to less than two right angles, then the two lines, if extended indefinitely, meet...."
This is known as the "parallel postulate." It was stated in much simpler terms by a Scottish mathematician named John Playfair, roughly a generation before Gauss began looking into the matter. Playfair said, "There is at most one line that can be drawn through another line at an external point."

Sometimes popularizers summarize this all as "parallel lines don't meet," but that is misleading. It may sound more like a tautology than an axiom.. If we understand parallel lines as any pair of lines that both pass through a common third line at 90 degree angle, though, then this is an accurate inference from the fifth axiom.

At any rate, one key thing about Euclid's fifth axiom is: There is no proof of it. That's why it has to be taken as an axiom! Another key thing to remember: it doesn't sound necessary. It never did. The other four axioms in Euclid seem unassailable in a way this one does not. For example: Euclid posits that it is possible in principle to draw a straight line from any point to any other point. That is the postulate that space is continuous. Another one: all right angles are equal to each other. Now, that one sounds like a tautology. Every right angle is a right angle.

But the fifth axiom, either as Euclid stated it or in Playfair's reworking, looks like something tacked on to make the system work.

This situation (as Ratcliffe sees things) is what induced Gauss to make trouble, which led ultimately to the idea of a Big Bang and an expanding cosmos. Ratcliffe seems to be saying that real space is Euclidean space, and that any other view, even the possibility of any other view, involves over-thinking things, letting our abstractions run away from us.

"Carl Friedrich Gauss (1777 - 1855) is remembered as the Prince of Mathematicians," he writes at one point, "and it is he who holds a close second place in my adulation, after Euclid."

Don't mess with number one, though. As we read further, we find that "simple life" reference amplified. It seems that Gauss earns our author's admiration due to the nature of the life he led, the fact that he was a good teacher whose students "revered him for his even temper and generous spirit," and so forth: not due to his researches, especially not due to his contributions to geometry.

I've gone on a bit long. I'll finish this line of thought tomorrow.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers