Skip to main content

The Twin Paradox

I recently read a book, or much of a book, called The Philosophy of Physics, by Tim Maudlin.



I say "much of it" because, quite frankly, I couldn't follow it and gave up on it well before the end.

But there were parts that I believe I did understand, and on the basis thereof I can say that this was a good book to read so soon  after reading Ratcliffe. Ratcliffe, as you may remember, had a quite idiosyncratic take on Euclidean and non-Euclidean geometries. It was an eccentricity that for me rather vitiated his efforts to contribute to cosmology.

Anyway: back to Maudlin. In one portion of the book he considers at some length the "twins paradox," a puzzle arising from, and often commented upon in the context of, the theory of relativity. 

Here it is in my understanding, not his. An astronaut takes off for a distant spaceport, travels at near the speed of light, so time slows. Comes back. He is now only, say, 1 year older than he was when he left. His stay-on-earth twin is (again, making up numbers) forty years older.

One is brought to see the plausibility of that through various inferences. But then one is supposed to say, "hey! isn't the premise of the underlying theory that motion is relative?" From the point of view of Paul, Peter was doing a lot of travelling over 40 years. From the point of view of Peter, presumably Paul and the rest of the earth population did a lot of travelling. Why isn't their situation symmetrical? And if it is, why should either be the older one now?


The usual answer to the questions raised by this paradox involves the acts of accelerating and decelerating. The twin in the spaceship accelerated on his way outbound, decelerated when he arrived at the spaceport, accelerated again when he started to trip home, decelerated again as he approached the earth. The situation is not symmetrical because the earth-bound twin didn't do any of this.

But Maudlin disagrees with that analysis of the paradox. It is true, he says, that acceleration is an asymmetry in the situation as described, but it isn't the critical one.

He sees the answer as one involving world-lines through space time. The "inertial" world line, the stay-at-home line, is straight. The travellers' world-line moves away from, then comes back to, intersection with the inertial line. In Euclidean space, we see the travellers' line inevitably as two lines, thus making up with the inertial line a triangle in which the sum of the length of the two non-inertial lines in necessarily greater than the length of the inertial line.

Now, this is the tricky part. Take any clock on the spaceship (or take the "clock" consisting of the rate at which a human being's cells age) as measuring the length of the line. We would expect (still thinking like Euclideans) that the traveler is the one who has aged more. But the key to the non-Euclidean geometry of relativity theory is that this is exactly reversed. The inertial line in the longer one. The traveller has taken a short-cut through space-time in coming back to earth. Thus his comparative youth, which is not at all a relative matter, forty years or one year later.

The conclusion? Relativity is not a relativism.

Comments

  1. hey, i read your post. it is very nice.i have also written a similar blog where i have explained this in very simple words. link to my blog is https://physicstalk1996.blogspot.com/2018/12/twin-paradox-tale-of-twins.html

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak