Skip to main content

Accounting Basics, Part Three




An issue quite analogous to depreciation is depletion. For businesses that operate by extracting resources from the ground, surely one of their most important assets is the expected amount of oil, coal, diamonds, or whatever-it-might be that is still down there, yet to be extracted, on the land owned or leased by the company for this purpose. Over time, as oil [let us say] is removed, necessarily the remaining oil under there is depleted.

The issue has often been politically contentious. Indeed, references to the oil depletion allowance in various stages of its development run like a Wagnerian motif through the various volumes of Robert Caro’s work on the life and times of Lyndon Johnson, who as both Representative and Senator from the oil-rich state of Texas was a stalwart defender of a very generous allowance for the tax accounting books, one which does not have to be duplicated in the financial accounting books.

But let’s stick to the latter.  One way in which accountants might value the remaining oil, or the somewhat-used-up conveyor belt for that matter, (we’ll just consider this for now as a hypothetical possibility) is by repeatedly marking them to their market value – at the end of every year or quarter or what-have-you. As each new period ends, the accountants could ask themselves, “how much can we get on the market for a conveyor belt like this?”

That is called a mark-to-market rule, and it has its attractions. If a firm could regularly mark to market the value of the conveyer belt, and if it could do so in a transparent way (that is, a way that would allow any interested observer to confirm that valuation) then it would have set at ease the minds of many a counter-party. Insurance companies and bankers would welcome the information. Marking to market would facilitate the securitization of the conveyer belt itself: that is, it would help the firm if it chose to offer the belt as collateral.

Unfortunately, just as there is no crystal ball to tell us how long the belt will last, so there is no conveyer-belt blue book to tell us how much it would be worth if sold. Constant appraisals [by hypothetical conveyer-belt appraisers] would represent an expenditure of time and money that may easily exceed the benefits.

There may be another consideration: market vicissitudes. Perhaps the market for conveyer belts has seized up, due to some quite temporary emergency. If our firm had to sell the belt today, the price we would get for it would be a disastrously low one, a “fire sale price”.  Would it be fair then to expect us to mark it down to that fire sale price?

For such assets as this accountants have long since shrugged at such questions and accepted rules of thumb telling them how long a productive asset may be expected to last, and discounted its original value, as measured by that sales price, a period at a time accordingly.

But let’s vary the facts a bit. Suppose a large chain of widget retailers has created a division that makes its own conveyor belts, thus freeing itself from the vicissitudes of its former vendors.  Then a new boss comes in and decides to tighten up the focus of the organization by selling off non-core assets. He spins off the conveyor belt division into a new company, CBD Inc.   

The widget-selling parent company retains an equity interest in CBD Inc.  Suppose it retains 30 percent ownership and sells the other 70.

Now it must list its share in CBD Inc. on its balance sheet. How does it value that?

If CBD itself goes public, if that other 70 percent of its equity is bought and sold daily on the New York Stock Exchange, then the question answers itself. The value of the 70 percent of the stock that trades on the market will serve as a metric for the value of the 30 percent that the parent corporation holds as an asset.

Inventory  

Let’s return to the list of assets in our hypothetical balance sheets above, and look to the next line on the list, below equipment. That line is inventory, and this term accountants define as the stock of merchandise at hand that a company holds ready to sell. This is often an important item on the asset side of the balance sheet, and the valuation of inventory can become a matter of intense controversy, especially during periods of price inflation.

In particular, consider last-in first-out valuation on the one hand and first-in first-out on the other (LIFO and FIFO).  Those names describe the distinction: a retailer using LIFO will match the value of a just-purchased item at wholesale against the sales value of the most recently sold item of the same kind. A retailer using FIFO will match the supplier’s price of the oldest “widget” still in the storeroom against the sales price of the most recent one just sold to a customer.

We have, let us say, 50 widgets in stock. The oldest of these we purchased a year ago for just $2 from our wholesaler/supplier. But it has been quite an inflationary year in the world of widgets, and the newest on stock we bought just yesterday at $3.50. 

A customer just bought one at our present retail price of $4.20. We now have $4.20 more in the till than we used to. But we have a less valuable inventory. How much less valuable? Under LIFO, we have to mark down the value of our inventory by $3.50: under FIFO, by just $2.

This difference would be an even bigger deal if we were discussing income statements than when discussing balance sheet, because in the former case it would be a matter of determining how much profit we’re making per widget.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak