Skip to main content

Animals as Machines



Rene Descartes believed that only humans have souls. Thus, only humans are capable of thought: animals are entirely mechanical.

When you think that your dog is thinking, then, you are actually just confused by the marvelous intricacy of the machinery.

I used to think that this was a rather straight-forward idea. There would be times when I thought it idiotic and times when I thought it represented a fairly subtle sort of mistake: but in either mood I thought it easily enough grasped. It was, as Descartes himself said of ideas he approved, "clear and distinct."

But recently I encountered an article by John Cottingham that persuades me that getting right what Descartes has to say about animals is a bit complicated. There are ambiguities here.

I should confess here that the Cottingham article is no very new contribution to scholarship. It was published in 1978, and has evaded my attention until this week. Still ... here we are.

 In Part V of RD's DISCOURSE he explains that living bodies in general (including our own) are machines, any one of which "having been made from the hands of God, is incomparably more orderly ... than any of those ... invented by men." Thus, as Descartes said in a letter to Henry More, "all the motions of animals originate from the corporeal and mechanical principle."

Our own bodily machine has a ghost rattling around inside of it, a ghost that can tell itself "I think" and therefore can become aware of --indeed, philosophically certain of -- its own existence. Animals don't have that.

All of this leads to the inference that there is an absolute difference between humans and animals, turning on who can be self conscious and who cannot. But it doesn't necessarily lead to the conclusion some have found therein, that animals are (as Kemp Smith has put it) "incapable of experiencing the feelings of well-being or the reverse, hunger or thirst...."

Cottingham raises the issue of the distinction between consciousness and self-consciousness.  Descartes, at the least, did not unambiguously conflate the two. Animals, their mechanical and soulless nature notwithstanding, may on Cartesian premises be conscious enough to feel.

Cottingham quotes a letter RD wrote to Newcastle: "[A]ll the things which dogs, horses, and monkeys are made to do are merely expressions of their fear, their hope, or their joy; and, consequently, they can do these things without any thought."

So "fear" for example is a feeling not a thought. It is consciousness of a sort but not self-consciousness.

Yet, as Cottingham also tells us, Cartesian metaphysics would be more logical and internally consistent if animals were without feeling. Allowing them consciousness introduces a "strange fuzziness" in Cartesian metaphysics. Not so clear or distinct any more.





Comments

  1. I would distinguish between physical "feelings" such as hunger, and emotional feelings such as fear. I could imagine the possibility of an animal without consciousness (not merely without self-consciousness) feeling hunger and consequently eating. It would be analogous to the way, when a car runs low on gas, a reservoir automatically opens to release more gas into the tank.

    But it is difficult to imagine an animal without consciousness feeling fear. Suppose that an animal encounters another animal. If he fears the other animal he flees; if he does not feel fear, he does not flee. Whether he feels fear depends upon his assessing whether the other animal is a threat to him, and he could not make that assessment without being conscious. The only way around that would be if God, when he created the animal, had programmed the animal's response to every situation he would encounter during his life.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Actually, God would not have to have programmed the animal's response to every situation at the time he created the animal. He could step in and determine the animal's response in each situation as it occurs. That would keep him pretty busy, considering the large number of animals around, but that shouldn't be a problem for someone who is omnipotent.

      Delete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak