Skip to main content

Principle of Plenitude




I recently encountered a critique of Arthur Lovejoy's well-known book on the "great chain of being."


I've discussed that book in this blog, focusing on what it says about theodicy, that is, efforts to justify the ways of God to man.


But the critic I encountered recently, Jaakko Hintikka, the fellow portrayed here, focuses on the "principle of plenitude."


So let's look at that for a moment, gentle reader. The P of P is one of the "unit ideas" in Lovejoy's account of the great chain. It is one of the atoms that came together to form that molecule.


In Lovejoy's formulation, the P of P is the idea that every kind of creature that is possible is also actual. In one form, this means that in the fullness of time, anything that is not the case now either once was the case or at some time will be the case, as when Descartes wrote that due to the laws of nature "matter takes on, successively, all the forms of which it is capable."


In another form, the principle has a more static significance -- the universe has always included all possibilities within some range. Maintaining this requires a certain level of abstraction in one's formulation, and the level it requires is a matter of some debate. But we can see how the notion of the P of P contributes to that of the Great Chain. There must be matter without life, life without motion, moving life (animals) without intellect, and intellectual animals as well, all because each is possible. Likewise with creatures we cannot observe. There must be intelligences without bodies (angels) because it is possible that there are.


Hintikka contends that Lovejoy's understanding of the P of P is defective "not just in its details but also in some of its main outlines."


He claims, for example, that Lovejoy erroneously believes Plato ascribed to the P of P and that Aristotle did not. On Hintikka's own view, Aristotle not only subscribed to the P of P, he argued for it and used it as a lemma in his philosophy. Whether Plato believed in the P of P, on the other hand, is not at all clear, at any rate he never "embraced" it in an unqualified way as his student did. Given the significance of those two men, this error is more than a detail, even if it is less than a "main outline," of Lovejoy's account.


What is more important, Hintikka contends that Lovejoy is too wedded to a static conception of the P of P. He thinks the more dynamic, evolutionary conception came along quite late in his story. But tis is perhaps because of Lovejoy's premise that the P of P is a true "unit idea." Once we can see that this atom splits, we can see that the dynamic reading was there from very early on.


This will suffice for today's cogitations.





Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak