Skip to main content

Robert Audi



Robert Audi is a contemporary exponent of intuitionism within the field of moral epistemology. That is, his answer to the question "how do we know what is right" involves an appeal to a quasi-sensory and non-inferential recognition one might call intuition for lack of a better term.

His 2013 book MORAL PERCEPTION is one of those that puts this view forward.

My understanding is that Audi specifically thinks of duties and their breach as the objects of this intuition. We intuit things like "lying is prima facie wrong." We neither infer it nor are we making a statement of subjective preference when we say such a thing. We intuit it and we are sensing something objectively true when we do so.

I think there is something both importantly right and importantly wrong in this. I think that it is appropriate to ground moral judgments in intuitions, but those intuitions are of the goodness of events, not the rightness of actions. Intuitionism, that is, works better with teleology rather than (as Audi would have it) with deontology.


Comments

  1. Two questions: (1) Would it change your point to replace "teleology" with "consequentialism"?, and (2) Putting aside epistemology and intuitionism, isn't deontology grounded in teleology or consequentialism? If a deontologist asserts that lying is wrong (prima facie or always, as Kant held), doesn't he do so because of the undesirable consequences of lying? What else could his condemnation of lying be based on, unless it is arbitrary?

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. If I am right about (2), then would deontology be the same as rule utilitarianism? Since I've never heard anyone assert that, I must be wrong about (2). If so, why?

      Also, I just substituted "utilitarianism" for "consequentialism," because I've never heard the term "rule consequentialism." Is there a type of consequentialism other than utilitarianism?

      Delete
  2. Henry. (1) Yes, I use teleology and consequentialism as synonyms. (2) Kant's argument as I understand it was that the telling of lies AS A UNIVERSAL LAW would be a disastrous one, because of course the species would lose the benefit of the ability to communicate. Thus, that can NOT become a universal law, whereas telling the truth can be. Since he had other (quite abstract) arguments for the proposition that right actions must be based upon universal law, this led him to the conclusion that a lie must always be wrong.

    That is different from rule utilitarianism, and both are different from Audi's intuitionism. Putting aside the latter: a rule utilitarian might argue that lies usually have more bad than good consequences, and that although there are exceptions they are rare. On that basis, he might argue that we're better off following the rule "never lie," or developing a habit of truth telling, even if this means that sometimes we will lose the benefit of an exception. We might also avoid the costs of a "false positive," of the situation in which we erroneously believe we're acting in an exceptional case.

    An intuitionist could argue that we have the intuitive sense that lying is wrong (as least prima facie) because natural selection has hard wired us for it, because inveterate liars would be weeded out by an environment in which other humans stop cooperating with them.

    ReplyDelete
  3. Christopher, from what you say, Kant and a rule utilitarian, although they would take different routes to arrive at the conclusion that one should never lie, would both arrive at that same conclusion. In practice, a rule utilitarian could incorporate exceptions in the rule; the rule might be, for example, never lie unless severe bodily harm or death would likely result. This would allow one to lie in the situation in which Kant said one should not lie: where a would-be murderer asks you where his potential victim is hiding. But couldn't Kant have formulated his universal law to incorporate that exception?

    ReplyDelete
  4. Henry,

    Probably. That is one of the classic counter-arguments to Kant, that he is gerrymandering the notion of universality, and that without selective gerrymandering the demand for universality becomes unhelpful. It sounds at best like a Teutonically pedantic restatement of the golden rule. It is appropriate to remind me that I should not lie to others because I don't like being lied to, but of course that hardly helps in the sort of extreme situation to which you allude.

    And as to a question you asked me earlier in this threat and I left unanswered: yes, there is a consequentialism other than utilitarianism. The classic example is called "perfectionism." I might believe in Nietzschean fashion that human ethics should be all about producing the Over-Man, someone or some state of things more perfect than us flawed humans. In such a case, though, rule consequentialism doesn't work. What are the "rules" that have shown themselves helpful in producing superior species'?

    There are other sorts of consequentialist. G.E. Moore called himself an "ideal utilitarian." The adjective was mean to cover a considerable deviation from the non-ideal sorts, and I believe Moore's self-labeling was not apt, that his "utilitarianism" was outside of the fold of that term as usually understood, and that it makes more sense to think of him as a pluralist consequentialist. And I consider myself a pluralist consequentialist as well.

    As to rule consequentialism, that is a label adopted by a prominent contemporary philosopher in the UK, Brad Hooker, of the University of Reading.

    ReplyDelete
  5. Discount for the usual typos above. The most amusing one is "threat" for "thread." That's why God made editors.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a maj...

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak...

Recent Controversies Involving Nassim Taleb, Part I

I've written about Nassim Taleb on earlier occasions in this blog. I'll let you do the search yourself, dear reader, for the full background. The short answer to the question "who is Taleb?" is this: he is a 57 year old man born in Lebanon, educated in France, who has been both a hedge fund manager and a derivatives trader. He retired from active participation from the financial world sometime between 2004 and 2006, and has been a full-time writer and provocateur ever since. Taleb's writings for the general public began where one might expect -- in the field where he had made his money -- and he explained certain financial issues to a broad audiences in a very dramatic non-technical way. Since then, he has widened has fields of study, writing about just about everything, applying the intellectual tools he honed in that earlier work. As you might have gather from the above, I respect Taleb, though I have sometimes been critical of him when my own writing ab...