Skip to main content

The "Modern Synthesis" in Evolutionary Biology


Theodosius Dobzhansky.jpg

A recent anthology by philosophers of science challenging the "modern synthesis" in evolution draws an intelligent review from NDPR, here:

https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/challenging-the-modern-synthesis-adaptation-development-and-inheritanc/

What had to be brought together was some sort of Darwinian account of evolution on the one hand and Mendelian genetics on the other.  The late 1930s and early 1940s were key, and the gelling of the synthesis involved a seminal book by  Theodosius Dobzhansky in 1937, and another by Ernst Mayr in 1942 The term "modern synthesis" was attached to such work in the subtitle of a book by Julian Huxley, also in 1942.

I'll quote the review directly for some institutional history: 

During this period significant institution building was taking place, coupled with theoretically significant gate-keeping. The Committee on Common Problems of Genetics, Paleontology, and Systematics, supported by a United States National Research Council, was launched in 1942 to establish a hitherto missing bridge between genetics and paleontology. It led to the formation of the Society for the Study of Evolution in 1946. The affiliated journal Evolution began appearing that same year. Mayr played key organizational roles in these developments that gave shape to the discipline of evolutionary biology.

I gather from the review that the various essays show the MS to be a pretty diffuse thing by now. It isn't especially meaningful to speak in Kuhnian terms of this as a "paradigm" for "normal science" and to ask about the candidates for the next revolution. But in general the synthesis is genocentric rather than phenocentric -- that is, it sees evolution as something that happens to and through gene lines rather than organisms. It generally still holds to the notion that variation is blind -- no gene ever undergoes a modification because that would be adaptive. Rather, it undergoes a blind modification and that is adopted by he environment as a successful modification. Further, the general presumption on issues of development is that one's DNA encodes the adult one in some sense 'ought to' grow up to be. If one doesn't mature into THAT phenotype, something has gone wrong. 

The reviewer quotes one of the authors in the book saying happily that the modern synthesis has been "capacious enough to embrace a Dobzhansky, a Mayr, a Ford, a Dawkins, and even a Gould."  

I've now mentioned Dobzhansky twice (three times including this sentence!)> I'll put an image of him at the top, then. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak