Skip to main content

What Makes Time Special?



The headline of this post, "What Makes Time Special?" Is the title of a recent book by philosopher Craig Callender, one of the co-winners this year of the Lakatos Award, for the best work in the philosophy of science.

With due respect to the other co-winner, Sabina Leonelli, my arbitrary spotlight of curiosity today falls on Professor Callender, perhaps in part just because his name looks a lot like "calendar," which is a great name to have if you're going to be writing about Time as a philosophical subject!

Callender begins the book in a striking way, "Time is a big invisible thing that will kill you," he writes. That sounds like a slightly morbid and slightly precocious child's effort to philosophize about time. I gather that is what Callender means for it to sound like.

I also gather, from only having skimmed the book, that Callender doesn't really present any other view of time more sophisticated than the one he starts off with. It IS a big invisible thing that will kill you.  That is not so much what makes it "special," though, as a phenomenological way of stating its specialness.

As to what makes it special, Callender's answer seems to be: our humanity. He does talk about the kinds of experiences of time that individuals of other species may have, and seems to think of that as a worthy subject of further research, but not one on which much progress has been made.

"Perhaps time doesn't flow in any interesting sense for the lobster." It flows for us, though, so it is reasonable for us to identify the fact of its flow, the phenomenology of time, to the fact that we are human.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak