Skip to main content

The Problem of Evil

Christ Pantocrator (Deesis mosaic detail)

I hope every reader of mine has had a fine Thanksgiving break and is ready for another work week. In New England, the home of the origin story of this feast, we certainly had great weather for it: weather harsh enough that we could think of ourselves as new settlers in a harsh dangerous land and show some Calvinist  fortitude in facing up to it!

The following may have some connection to Calvinism, but not much. I'll inflict it upon you anyway. 

A young friend of mine, in college, taking a course on the philosophy of religion, was recently assigned to write a paper about the dispute between Mackie and Plantinga over free will and the problem of evil. 

Mackie has argued (as have many others, but the Mackie version of the case has become a focal point of recent debate) that it is logically impossible to reconcile three claims: that an omnipotent God exists; that this is also an ideally benevolent being; and that evil exists. Any theology with any hope of plausibility will have to let go of one of those three points. Mackie in his essay considers the "free will defense" as a way of reconciling the three, and gives his reasons for rejecting it. 

Alvin Plantinga wrote a book-length reply to Mackie.

Anyway, I'm NOT stealing from my young friend's paper. And he has already turned the paper in, so he can't steal from this, either. These are some thoughts of mine on the general subject. Regular readers of this blog may find them familiar. 

 Mackie finds the free-will solution incoherent. He replies to it that there is no contradiction between having free will and doing the right thing. Thus, there cannot be a contradiction between having free will and always doing the right thing. Finally, since there is no contradiction involved, an omnipotent God could have created a world in which people have the power of free will AND they always choose to do good. Since God didn’t create such a world, the problem of evil is still with us (or with such theists).  


Mackie says that the reason some great minds have found this bad argument persuasive is that they confuse two different meanings of the phrase “free will.” On the one hand, they consider free will a great good, the power to make up our own minds. On the other hand, though, they see free will as requiring an element of randomness in human activity. If by “free” one means “random," then one can say that of course free humans can’t always act courageously or sympathetically, just as proper coins can’t be expected always to come up heads.


Yet it is a simple confusion to think about freedom as requiring randomness and to value freedom. What is the value of a coin-flip notion of the human will? The fact of coming up heads on a particular toss is neither a good thing nor a bad thing nor is it obvious why human actions (or character traits) should ever be considered good or bad if they, too, are “sheer randomness.”  


Once the confusion about randomness is edited out, what one is left with is freedom as the power to make up our minds and act accordingly, and there is no reason why an omnipotent Being could not have created humans who would always do so perfectly, thereby acting freely as well as rightly So: the problem of evil remains unsolved.
 
Plantinga contends in response that the price for creating a world in which moral good is possible is the creation of a world in which moral evil is also possible.

This amount to arguing, in Mackie’s terms, that it is not after all a confusion to connect moral freedom with randomness. Randomness is part of a single coherent idea of freedom. Plantinga, then, is within the tradition of thought known as incompatibilism -- the idea that determinism and freedom (or, in a variant way of putting the point, determinism and moral responsibility) are mutually inconsistent. This is a traditional view famously expounded by William James in the lecture “The Dilemma of Determinism” in 1884, though Plantinga is putting it to an unJamesian use.

We have to have the randomness within our decision-making in order to believe, when we have produced a result, that things could have been otherwise. And we have to have that could-have-been-otherwise understanding in order to judge the result good and bad, or to judge our actions right and wrong. Thus, the creation of a world in which evil things could happen is part of the price even an omnipotent God has to pay in order to create a world in which good things can happen.   

Plantinga puts this argument in “modal” terms: that is, in terms of the set of possible worlds. There may indeed be a possible world in which humans endowed with free will act rightly all the time. But there is no possible world in which God created humans with free will and ensured that they would act rightly all the time. That he did the latter would imply he had not done the former.

Plantinga has the better of the argument on incompatibilism. I agree with the common intuition of James, Karl Popper, Isaiah Berlin, Robert Kane and others, that freedom implies other ways things might have been, and that this implies an element of randomness. Fortunately, quantum mechanics makes this randomness seem plausible.

Nonetheless, there are weaknesses in Plantinga’s broader case. For example, it isn’t the case that everything we consider evil follows from any intentional human action. We might well call cancer and its impact evil. Yet cancer is part of the natural world in which God has set us, not any decision of ours.

To say “some people need to get cancer in order that they can show courage” or that some people have to get cancer so others can display sympathy and other virtues, and that this justifies such evils is, at best, counterintuitive and at worst positively callous.

The best conclusion is the one that Mackie hints at early in his essay: that theists should give up on the notion of God’s omnipotence. Consider that God may just be a name for the fact (if we decide that it is a fact) that the universe has a spiritual dimension, irreducible to the observable realities of matter and physical energy. Indeed, one might reject a dichotomy between polytheism and monotheism. One might well say that God is the unitary name for this spiritual dimension of the cosmos, “the gods” is the pluralistic name for it, and that the dimension in question may be in some respects singular, in other respects plural.

Given such a conception, there is no good reason to posit the omnipotence of God. One might simply say that Rabbi Kushner has it right, in WHEN BAD THINGS HAPPEN TO GOOD PEOPLE. 'God does some important things, but he can’t do everything.'

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak