Skip to main content

Capital punishment and the insanity defense


Image result for trial by jury


The US Supreme Court is back to hearing cases. 

On its very first day of the new session, it heard a dandy. KAHLER v. KANSAS asks whether, especially in the context of capital punishment, a state can constitutionally take the insanity defense off the table. 


The 14th amendment to the US Constitution provides that “no state shall … deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law.”
The Supreme Court has long held that the due process requirement is most stringent for the first of those threats, a proposed deprivation of life: that is, there is a “super due process” required for application of the death penalty.
In a matter that the Court will hear Monday, lawyers for a death row inmate will argue that a Kansas law abolishing the insanity defense in a capital matter deprived their client of this necessary super due process of law, and they will ask that his sentence be overturned.
You might say, "ah, surely with the two new Trump appointed Justices the death-penalty hawks will win the day, will they not?" 
I would answer "not necessarily." The convention by which one counts heads on the court as "liberal" or "conservatives" and predicts the outcome of decisions based on how those ideological numbers comes out is very unreliable. Further, neither Gorsuch nor Kavanaugh owes the Prez who nominated him a darned thing, as the history of SCOTUS confirms. 
But let's not go back deep into history. Just look to last year's term, which featured TIMBS v. INDIANA and the Flowers case.
In TIMBS, SCOTUS had to decided whether the excessive fines clause of the bill of rights limits the states. It had never been incorporated into the 14th. But now ... it has been. The decision to do so was unanimous. Gorsuch wrote a concurring opinion saying "there can be no serious doubt that the Fourteenth Amendment requires the States to respect the freedom from excessive fines." 
In FLOWERS v. MISSISSIPPI, also last term, SCOTUS found in a capital punishment context that there was clear error at the trial court level in that the judge had allowed for the peremptory exclusion of black jurors by the prosecution. A Trump appointee, Kavanaugh, wrote the opinion for the court on that one. 

In the oral argument on KAHLER Monday, it was a George W. Bush appointee, Justice Roberts, who observed: "if it's historically established that you cannot punish people who don't know the difference between right and wrong, that certainly sounds like something that is rooted in the conscience and would be ranked as fundamental." 
Let's hope for another defeat here for the ideological-tagging theory of jurisprudence. 



Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak