Skip to main content

The Supreme Court Term: Sebelius at last

Now I really must say something about NFIB v. Sebelius, SCOTUS' big Obamacare decision, or you will think me a shirker.



Let's start with this datum: Chief Justice John Roberts is only the second SCOTUS Justice in the institution's history with that surname. Its a fairly common surname in English-speaking countries, so I don't know whether 2-out-of-112 is a lot or suspiciously few. Anyway, the coincidence seems worth mentioning because the previous Justice Roberts [Owen Roberts, a Hoover appointee on the court from 1930 to 1945] has gone down in history as the Justice who made the big switch, who turned the court from one with an anti-New Deal 5 Justice majority into one with a pro-New Deal 5 Justice majority by his own change of heart under political pressure in 1937.

Reference Guide

The usual accounts of that "switch in time" are sometimes too simply and broadly written, and certainly it wasn't all about Roberts. Chief Justice Hughes played a pivotal role too, as did mortality. (By the time of the attack on Pearl Harbor, Owen Roberts was the only appointee of any president other than FDR still on the court.)

But the fact is, in 1936 in US v. BUTLER, a 5 member majority of the court struck down parts of the Agricultural Adjustment Act. Roberts was part of that majority. Interestingly, in light of 2012 events, the Roosevelt administration had argued that the AAA was legitimate as an exercise of the Congressional taxing power. The court refused to understand the taxing power that broadly.

After the introduction of court-packing legislation early the following year, Roberts never again voted against any New Deal legislation. And no further such legislation was ever again struck down by the court.

Also worth mentioning in this connection, the administration revived the farm planning regime of the old AAA, defending the revised version on the theory not that it was a tax but that it was a regulation of interstate commerce. Roberts, and the court in general, accepted that, in the (somewhat absurdly reasoned) Wickard v. Filburn case.

Two Justices named Roberts.

Okay, the name thing is a meaningless coincidence. Still ... in NFIB v. Sebelius, the newer Roberts (who had been admired among conservatives in connection with the big campaign-finance decision of 2010, Citizens United) is on their fecal-matter list now. They believe that it was under the threat that the Obama administration would wage a campaign against the independence of SCOTUS that Roberts switched his own vote -- that he left the company of his conservative colleagues and decided the health-insurance mandate in particular could pass muster if the means of its enforcement, the so-called penalty for not insuring one's self, is instead understood as a tax.

So the first switch-in-time by the first Roberts involved the abandonment of a tax-based justification, and adoption of a commerce clause justification, for what the elective branches wanted to do. This one moved exactly the other way.

All this appeals to the pattern-finding instinct of my mind, as you've no doubt seen already.

I had planned to write only a three part discussion of the Supreme Court term just past, letting this entry serve as the last part. But I see now that this won't do. A bit more tomorrow.

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers