Skip to main content

The Analytic/Synthetic Dichotomy

In a long footnote in The Principles of Psychology, William James discussed the analytic/synthetic dichotomy.

He consigned it to a footnote because he was sick of the subject, thinking it a "waste of ink and paper." W.V.O. Quine would come to much the same conclusion, 60 years later, after much more paper and ink had been employed.

James provides us in the course of this footnote with a geometrical example of why the effort to maintain a consistently dichotomous relationship between these two sorts of statements is such a waste.

"No one will say that such analytic judgments as 'equidistant lines can nowhere meet' are pure tautologies. The predicate is a somewhat new way of conceiving as well as of naming the subject. There is something 'ampliative' in our greatest truism, our state of mind is richer after than before we have uttered them."

Now, if he had written "parallel lines can never meet" he would he stated neither a synthetic nor an analytic truth but … a falsehood, as we since Einstein's work have come to understand the
space of this cosmos. In standard definition, parallel lines are lines that each cross some third line at a 90 degree angle. If we draw three lines on a piece of paper that meet this qualification,
the two that are "parallel" will never cross each other because they'll stay the same distance away from each other at every point (they'll stay "equidistant" in James word). But notice, equidistance
doesn't define parallellism. The two 90 degree angles define it.

This is why, if you had a piece of paper the size of a continent, the experiment might no longer work. If the think of the equator as the base line, then the various meridians cross it at 90 degree angles,
yet they come closer to each other the further they get from the equator, and they intersect with each other, at the two poles. Likewise, if space itself is curved, then we can't be certain that
parallel lines however abstractly conceived will always fail to intersect.



The development of non-Euclidean geometry actually preceded Einstein's life and James' working life. Two great mathematicians, Gauss and Lobachevsky, were working out such systems in the early
1850s. Still, Gauss and Lobachevsky thought they were engaged in a thoroughly hypothetical endeavor, pure mathematics. They had no idea they might be describing real space. This shows that a pragmatic theory of truth or knowledge has to be fairly subtle to accommodate such situations. G & L weren't doing or trying to do anything "useful" in any very mundane sense of that word.

James didn't have any inkling of the Einsteinian revolution about to engulf our understanding of the physical world, and he had only a nodding acquaintance with the then-recent developments in geometry that paved the way for it. So we are left to speculate why he said "equidistant" there instead of "parallel." At any rate, it was a lucky word choice, because it has prevented people from saying "what an obsolete example" and writing it off.

Clearly, in anyone's geometry, if two lines really are two, and they really are equidistant, they never meet. If they are two than they aren't zero distance apart. So they are some distance apart, and by
definition will always stay that difference apart (however curvy that might require them to become, in a curvy space!), so they never meet.

I think James' conclusion is quite germane. Even with "two equidistant lines will never meet" we can see that the predicate adds something to our grasp of the subject, helps us to grasp it in a
different light than we otherwise might.


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak