Skip to main content

A Causal Theory of Knowledge I

 


Recently in this blog I spoke of the death of Prof. Gettier, and of post-Gettier problems in epistemology. Prompted by a response to that post, I will in today's and tomorrow's entry go further on this subject. 

My own views have changed in quite recent months, in large part through my discovery of Alvin Goldman's essay, "A Causal Theory of Knowing" from 1967, only four years after Gettier's famous essay. 

Goldman looked at only a piece of the puzzle, the knowledge of the perceived world. He set aside the question of what it means to know, for example, that 45 + 303 = 348. He was concerned with knowing something like "this leaf is green." 

If knowledge is "justified true belief," then I know this leaf is green if and only if (a) the leaf is in fact green, (b) I believe that it is green, and (c) I can see the leaf, and (say) I have recently had my eyes checked so I am confident in the health of my vision. Note that the justification element is interior to my belief system. Things like my memory of my recent visit to the ophthalmologist, and my confidence in HIS qualification, may come in here. 

But Gettier had complicated that account, and Goldman sees the complexity as arising from the internal nature of the idea of justification. CAUSATION, on the other hand, is external. I know that this leaf is green if and only if (a') the leaf is in fact green, (b') I believe that it is green, and (c') facts about the leaf stand in an appropriate causal relationship with the development of my belief. 

A broad definition of when the causal relationship is appropriate would, of course, be tricky. But let us stick to this example. This is New England and it is not yet October. The leaves have lots of chlorophyll in them and this means that they absorb light at the two ends of the visible spectrum and reflect back light in the center. That means that my eye takes in light of that wave length. We don't need to concern ourselves with our internal beliefs and ophthalmologists to judge that the way the world is has caused me to believe something truly about the way the world is. I have perceptual knowledge.  

What can I say about 45 + 303? We might carry Goldman's idea through in a straightforward way if we are Platonists, or rather Pythagoreans about the nature of number. But I am not and I doubt many of my readers are, either. More on this tomorrow.  

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak