Skip to main content

Overlooked Supreme Court decisions on what not to decide



At some time next month I will offer you my usual annual reflections on this Supreme Court term. 

I make this note in advance, about a case SCOTUS has decided NOT to hear. 

On June 21, the Supreme Court declined to take up the case of MONSANTO v. HARDEMAN.  

In this matter a Californian man named Edwin Hardeman alleged RoundUp, a Monsanto product, had caused his cancer. 

Hardeman received an award from a federal district court, applying California state law, of $25 million after a jury trial. But Monsanto has appealed, claiming that the matter is preempted by federal law, and the US EPA has concluded that the herbicide does not pose "any reasonable risk to man or the environment."

Monsanto appealed, and the 9th Circuit held for plaintiff.  The US, under Trump, sought to intervene and take Monsanto's side before SCOTUS. The government, under Biden, has indicated that it takes Hardeman's view and wants the award to stand. 

SCOTUS has decided not to hear the matter. This means presumably that Hardeman keeps his judgment and will get his money. 

What else might it mean?  

A Court in No Hurry

It might mean that this Court is in no hurry to narrow the scope of state law on torts. That is good news. That it is signalled by a dog that did NOT bark in the nighttime is, simply, what it is. 

In the news coverage on the day of the decision not to hear Monsanto, the SCOTUS orders and decisions were overwhelmed by a lot of other matters (from Ukraine news to a new round of revelations from the Jan. 6 committee). Furthermore, even when the Court was mentioned that day, the marquee case was the "free exercise" ruling on a dispute that arose in Maine. 

Of course, subsequent decisions that I WILL discuss in my annual reflections further overshadowed this. 

But I will note for whatever value my noting might have that I think the Court's non-interference with Hardeman's pursuit of his rights is ... a good thing.  

The Second Matter

Yesterday, June 27, the court AGAIN, for the second time in a week, declined to take up the issue of Round-Up. This time the case was  MONSANTO CO. v. PILLIOD. The underlying facts were much the same (and again it arose out of California). The additional Thing to Know in this case is that Monsanto wanted to argue that the punitive-damages award it had been hit with in this case was a violation of the due process clause. (It was a multiple of four of the compensatory part of the award).  

That difference justifies no distinction.  


Comments

  1. Having formerly worked on questions of tort law and federal preemption, but not having kept up nor read Monsanto v. Hardeman, my sense is that the EPA conclusion that the herbicide does not cause cancer does not prevent a jury from finding that it does, unless Congress said otherwise. The EPA's conclusion is evidence for the jury to consider, but not conclusive.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. To clarify, by "unless Congress said otherwise," I meant, "unless Congress said that EPA's conclusion is conclusive and blocks tort suits."

      Delete
  2. Very enlightening. And a timely choice, on your part. I have ideas on this, which I will hold, for now. Have harped on the current controversy, to no effect and without comment, agreement or rebuttal. No one affiliated or connected in any way to ' the conservancy' wants to acknowledge my observations or questions. Participatory democracy is sterile when those governed have to rely upon representatives who do not participate. Seems to me.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak