Skip to main content

Refusing to block the block on a bar





Newsweek offers the following confusing prose, about a case out of Arizona. Italics added. 

"The court [SCOTUS] issued an order related to a case raised by the Republican National Committee asking the justices to block a lower-court order that blocked enforcement of a 2022 law that would bar registered voters who have not previously provided proof of citizenship from voting in presidential elections, or by mail in any federal elections." The order declined to do so. (Subject to a qualification I'll get to later.)

All these negative signs. It's algebra. Two negative signs is a positive number.  Three negative signs is a negative again. Four negative signs (counting now the underlying law as the first negative) give us a positive result again. The people whose ability to vote was contested, CAN vote. 

The law says certain people can't vote.

A lower court said to Arizona "don't enforce that!" So those people can vote. 

The state asked the Justices to block THAT order, allowing enforcement, dis-allowing those votes. 

The court decided not to do that.  So the court's decision seems to end the matter for this election cycle and the vote count will be somewhat higher than it otherwise would have been.

Got it.   

Meanwhile, outside the domain of that particular sentence ... the court's order was in a manner of speaking a split one. It granted Arizona's authority to enforce a certain aspect of the law, but denied it authority to enforce another more hotly contested aspect of the law.  

Specifically, the law requires people registering to vote to use a state form to provide proof of citizenship (its prospective side) and at the same time sought to bar voters who hadn't done that, who had used a standard federal form, from voting in presidential elections in that state (the disenfranchising side). The above algebra, on how the court declined to block the block on a bar, applies to the disenfranchising part of the law.  The prospective side of the law has been upheld. 

Then there were the dissenters, who would have denied Arizona's request in full. There were four of them. This is where we get to something intriguing. 

(1) all of the Justices agreed to refuse the nub of what the RNC asked for, disenfranchisement;

(2) Five justices (almost all of the 'usual suspect' conservatives) decided to allow a victory on the prospective side;

(3) Four of the Justices --' liberals plus one -- wanted the state's defeat to be more complete.

So ... who was the plus one? Cue the Notre Dame theme song.

 "Justice Sotomayor, Justice Kagan, Justice Barrett, [italics added again] and Justice Jackson would deny the application in full," the order reads. All and only the women on the court, including the Trump appointee. 

Nice gender gap you got there, SCOTUS. The one woman within the usual conservative majority is the one Justice who splits off from that to join the all-women dissenting group. 

Anyway, you can get beyond Newsweek by going to the full account here: SCOTUSblog

Or reading the decision here: 082224zr_n75p.pdf (supremecourt.gov) It is brief and unsigned. The Court is on its summer break, after all. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak