Skip to main content

The law of the excluded middle, Part I


This is the first in a projected three-part series about the law of the excluded middle, a (disputed) logical principle according to which, for any well-defined  proposition, either the proposition is true or it is false.  Today I will explain the law in question and offer a classical argument for its validity. On another day (not tomorrow, I assure you): I will explain why I do not believe that argument is a strong one and why we might want to allow for violations of this LEM. When I get around to Part III, I will discuss how the dispute feeds into political philosophy and certain questions about the legitimate regulation of markets.

So ... let us proceed. 

When it seems that a proposition IS both true and false, or is neither, and in either case is in violation of this law, various remedies are available: the proposition in question might just be nonsense (as for example the claim that the Jabberwocky has a frumious Bandersnatch), it might embed a false premise (as for example the premise that France has a contemporary King who might either be bald or not), or it may be ambiguous (as for example the claim that days are 24 hours long).

Sticking with that last example for a moment: the word "day" in English can refer either to the whole of a planetary rotation, as from one midnight to the next, or it can refer to the period of light from sunrise to sunset.  In the one case, our above proposition is true, in the other it is false. Thus the old scholastic saying, sometimes quoted by William James, "if you think you have found a contradiction you must make a distinction." 

Allowing for all of that within the adjective "well-defined," none of those examples directly challenges the law of the excluded middle. 

There is no doubt that the law -- or rather the presumption -- of the excluded middle can be a useful heuristic pressing us to review premises and define terms -- still, IS it a law?  An ironclad law?  Why should we decree it so?    

C.I. Lewis, a great mid-20th-century philosopher whose Ph.D.  supervisor was Josiah Royce, offered an argument for excluding any middles. His argument has come to be known as the principle of explosion.  The idea is that if we accept even one seemingly innocuous contradiction into our worldview, everything explodes, because literally ANYTHING can be true.

The proof -- as applied to the seemingly harmless contradiction "all lemons are yellow" and "not all lemons are yellow" goes roughly like this:

1. Not all lemons are yellow -- by assumption.

2. All lemons are yellow -- also by assumption.

3. The two-part disjunction "all lemons are yellow or unicorns exist" must be true, since the word "or" means that it doesn't depend on unicorns and we have presumed lemons are yellow. 

4. Since we also presumed that not all lemons are yellow we have to infer that the first part of the disjunction is false, so in order for the whole disjunction to be true, unicorns must exist. 

5. In case you are fine with the inference that unicorns exist, consider that procedure can be repeated for any second statement, i.e. "all lemons are yellow or the Green Bay Packers went undefeated in the 2024-25 season." Thereby proving the truth of anything we wish to put into that second spot of the disjunction. I have it on good authority the Packers lost six times that season. 

6. This explosion of absurd "truths" is intolerable, so we must reject the proposition that both (1) and (2) above can be true.  Which is what was to be proved.   

But perhaps we can save our double assumption about lemons without either re-writing the Packers season or discovering unicorns.  Maybe?  More later.  


Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a maj...

The Lyrics of "Live Like You Were Dying"

Back in 2004 Tim McGraw recorded the song "Live Like You were Dying." As a way of marking the one-decade anniversary of this song, I'd like to admit that a couple of the lines have confused me for years. I could use your help understanding them. In the first couple of verses, the song seems easy to follow. Two men are talking, and one tells the other about his diagnosis. The doctors have (recently? or a long time ago and mistakenly? that isn't clear) given him the news that he would die soon. "I spent most of the next days/Looking at the X-rays." Then we get a couple of lines about a man crossing items off of his bucket list. "I went sky diving, I went rocky mountain climbing, I went two point seven seconds on a bull named Fu Man Chu." Then the speaker -- presumably still the old man -- shifts to the more characterological consequences of the news. As he was doing those things, he found he was loving deeper and speaking sweeter, and givin...

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak...