Skip to main content

The law of the excluded middle, Part II

 


Those who would read the following should really have first read the first part, posted here on March 28th.  I'm going to dive into the middle of material today without reviewing that.  Ready? Let's go.

How have defenders of a middle choice (between true and false, EVEN for some well-formed propositions) defended that possibility against C.I. Lewis' critique?

Well, to begin, they note that any effort to prove something involves premises.  To the extent that the law itself (we will call it LEM for short) is supposed -- as it is supposed by many -- to be a foundational premise in logic, it of course cannot be proven.  If Lewis has actually proven LEM, it must have been by discovering other deeper premises, and turning LEM into a lemma, so to speak, a steppingstone on the path from some important truths to others.

In fact, the Lewis "explosion argument" takes it as a premise that every sentence entails the disjunction of itself and any other sentence. This is known as the principle of addition. It means that if we accept the proposition "the earth is spherical" we must accept the truth of the disjunction "the earth is spherical or unicorns exist" -- "the earth is spherical or the Packers went undefeated last season" and so forth.  Since the earth is spherical, any sentence of that form is true.    

This, the principle of addition, is what Lewis employs as a lever.  If we accept any contradiction, then the principle of addition allows us to create such true sentences which in turn end up exploding the whole idea of truth, or of falsity. 

But all this ensures is that anyone who really wants LEM as a firm part of a logical system might make the principle of addition a more fundamental premise and deduce LEM from it. It doesn't prove that we need either of them, or not in the direct form with which we've been working.  LEM as I noted in our Part I is a useful heuristic and it might be well to keep it around in some modified form.  Likewise with the principal of addition. If we modify one, we modify the other.  But that is all that Lewis really proved here.  

In circumstances in which we are tempted to say "it is both the case that A is true and that the negation of A is true" we ought to be careful about taking either half of that conjunction and joining it to a random disjunction of the form "A is true and B".  With that understood, the creation of non-binary notions of truth and falsehood may proceed undaunted by the feared explosion. 

At this moment, I should show some appreciation to the philosopher Jc Beale, whose communications have helped me clarify my thoughts on this matter.  Thank you, sir. 

One more brief point.  There are arguments for "truth gluts" on the one hand, and there are arguments for "truth gaps" on the other. A truth gap is a situation in which some well-formed A is neither true nor false.  There is no truth about A.  A certain quantity of chin hair is both a beard and a non-beard. A truth glut is a situation in which some well-formed sentence is both true and false.  There is a glut of truth about A. The hair is a beard and it is a non-beard.  Some logicians who propound a non-binary logic are interested in the truth gluts, some in the truth gaps.  The LEM as stated denies the possibility of either. 

Professor Beale advocates for a logic with both gaps and gluts. 

Examples? Aside from hairs that may and/or may not be a beard? Consider Zeno's paradoxes such as the movement of an arrow.  It may well be both true and false to say that the arrow is exactly at point X at this moment. Indeed, accepting that truth glut may be a defining characteristic of motion in time.

Our Part III will bring political philosophy into the discussion. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a maj...

The Lyrics of "Live Like You Were Dying"

Back in 2004 Tim McGraw recorded the song "Live Like You were Dying." As a way of marking the one-decade anniversary of this song, I'd like to admit that a couple of the lines have confused me for years. I could use your help understanding them. In the first couple of verses, the song seems easy to follow. Two men are talking, and one tells the other about his diagnosis. The doctors have (recently? or a long time ago and mistakenly? that isn't clear) given him the news that he would die soon. "I spent most of the next days/Looking at the X-rays." Then we get a couple of lines about a man crossing items off of his bucket list. "I went sky diving, I went rocky mountain climbing, I went two point seven seconds on a bull named Fu Man Chu." Then the speaker -- presumably still the old man -- shifts to the more characterological consequences of the news. As he was doing those things, he found he was loving deeper and speaking sweeter, and givin...

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak...