Skip to main content

What Herbert Spencer Really Believed

Herbert Spencer - Wikipedia

Herbert Spencer is often called a “Social Darwinist.” I have called him that myself, and will probably do so  often in the future as well, because that has become the traditional term and it is sometimes necessary to abide by conventions in order to  make oneself understood. 
But I have come to believe that the term is inapt. Two other labels suggest themselves as superior. If one is looking for a label Spencer would accept for his own social/ethical views, the term "rational utilitarianism" would work. If one doesn't care to ask his permission, social Lamarckianism will also apply. 
Spencer's works on relevant subjects include SOCIAL STATICS (1851), THE STUDY OF SOCIOLOGY (1873), and MAN VERSUS THE STATE (1884).
Spencer called his own view “rational utilitarianism,” because -- as one might guess -- he believed utilitarians before him had been inadequately rational. He did identify the good with happiness, and that identification was associated for him with a belief that all creatures naturally seek preservation and reproduction, and that our sense of what makes us happy is biologically determined to direct us to serving those ends. 
Since humans are rational animals, we engage in practical reasoning, figuring out how to make ourselves happy and live with each other through certain rules of thumb that become common sense over time. This impetus leads us toward contract and away from status — it leads us to pay less attention generation by generation to the station into which we were born or that in which the fellow next to us was born, and more attention to what we can give to and get from one another via voluntary agreements. Further (since Spencer was as I noted a Lamarckian) he believed that these commonsense rules were not only culturally heritable, they were even genetically heritable, If I have figured out that contract is preferable to status, my kids will probably understand that more easily than I did, and their kids more easily still.
You may properly consider this a derivation of ethics (those commonsense principles we have all learned over time) from the implicit order found in nature (the environment that makes their exercise successful).

If I have reconstructed his thought accurately (I will refrain from recounting the scholarly debates on the subject over the last 150 years or so), this is an internally plausible body of thought. I stress the adverb "internally." Factors external to the body of thought have rendered it implausible. Lamarckianism has fallen into disrepute, for one thing. More so: In light of 21st century biology, any idea that evolution, whatever exactly its mechanism, contributes to such cognitive specifics as a recognition of the value of contracts, or even the value of keeping one's promises, seems absurd. 


Comments

  1. Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes cites Spencer's SOCIAL STATICS in his dissent in Lochner v. New York (1905): "The Fourteenth Amendment does not enact Mr. Herbert Spencer's Social Statics." Holmes was dissenting from the Court's finding a right to contract in the U.S. Constitution, which rendered unconstitutional a state law limiting the number of hours that a bakery could require its employees to work.

    ReplyDelete
  2. True. One odd thing about that: SOCIAL STATICS was far from the most germane of Spencer's books for that proposition. Either of the other two I mentioned would have been more germane. SOCIAL STATICS was a work of Spencer's wild long-haired youth, and it attracted favorable attention from such as Leo Tolstoy for its treatment if the "Land Question," its anti-landlord sentiments. One might imagine one of the members of the Lochner majority muttering "we sure as heck don't mean to incorporate THAT Spencer, anyway." But some suspect that notorious comment was a bit of a personal joke on Holmes' part, confident that the members of the majority wouldn't pick up on it because they didn't read that sort of book.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak