Skip to main content

Causation or Justification?

 


In philosophical writings about epistemology today there is a rather big to-do about internalist versus externalist accounts of knowledge.

I'll define the distinction here speaking very roughly. 

To an internalist, I know X to be the case if and only if (a) X is the case, (b) I believe X, and (c) I have a good reason, or warrant, or justification, to believe X.

To an externalist, on the other hand, I know X to be the case if and only if (a) X is the case, (b) I believe X, and (c) the reason why I believe X has an appropriate causal connection with X. 

The point of the labels is that justification (or whatever a particular theorist in this line may call it) is internal to my state of mind as the believer-of-X.  Causation may be entirely external to my state of mind. 

Direct sense perception provides the simplest example.  I form a belief that the leaves of this tree in front of me are green. It IS the case that they are green. The reason why I believe them to be green has a causal connection to their being green -- sunlight of the wavelength we call "green" just bounced off the leaf and entered my eyes. 

In this case, what modern folks who have passed some quite basic science courses mean by green is, roughly, surfaces off of which waves of just that length bounces. So one could hardly get a closer connection between (a) and (b). 

In such a case, the internalist might analyze the situation somewhat differently. He might say it is the case that the leaf is green, I believe that the leaf is green, and this belief is justified because I have consistently found my eyesight to be reliable and I have looked carefully at the leaf in good white light. the causal connection is at least somewhat less explicit here, the stuff internal to the believer's belief system is more explicit.  

What difference does it make? Why should I concern myself with internalism versus externalism?

Muddling up several possible answers here, I will point. Knowledge is often understood as a pyramid -- certain levels are more basic than others. Perhaps when we are young children we are already having experiences that are laying the bottom bricks, and later layers of brick have to be put on top of the layers already established, and if we live long enough we build toward a sky-high peak. Maybe the lucky get to shout "I understand it all now!" just before they die, as the final break, a peaked one, is put at the top. That kind of progressive optimistic view of knowledge, I imagine, is only possible given externalism. Because a literal pyramid always rests on something, such as the hardened sand where a fecund river valley meets a desert. The level hardened ground supports the pyramid, but is itself outside of the pyramid. Some external processes have to exist to get our reasonings started, however elaborate they may then turn out to be. 


   

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers