Skip to main content

A new meaning for the word "incompatibilism"

 


The word "incompatibilism" has a distinctive meaning to many students of, and scholars in ,philosophy. 

It arises in debates about determinism and moral responsibility.  

The key question, as I understand the debate, is this: is the notion of strict behavioral determinism consistent with our ordinary and strongly held intuitions about moral responsibility? 

There are some who say "no, the two are not compatible, and the moral intuitions are worth keeping: fortunately we CAN keep them, because strict behavioral determinism is wrong." 

There are others who say, "no, the two are not compatible -- and strict behavioral determinism is right, so we'll have to say goodbye to the moral intuitions and learn to live without them."

Both of those are incompatibilists, however much they quarrel with one another.   

There are still others who say, "Yes, strict determinisms is compatible with those intuitions,  so it need not at all disturb us to recognize that strict determinism is right."

I have discussed that argument here many times. [And, by way of reminder, continue to side with incompatibilist determinism.] I only bring it up now, though, to say that the philosophers Jonas Christensen and Umut Baysan have proposed using the same term, incompatibilism, in a different context. Here is a link to their essay: https://www.academia.edu/32558289/Why_Incompatibilism_about_Mental_Causation_is_Incompatible_with_Non_Reductive_Physicalism_Inquiry_forthcoming_?email_work_card=interaction-paper

If their terminology spreads, future philosophy textbooks may have to carefully distinguish the two uses of the term, because they involve related questions. 

The question Christenson and Baysan look at is: do mental events cause physical events? Does the fact of my hunger (interpreted as a mental and so in some sense an intangible event) cause a physical event as my arm stretches out to pluck an apple from the tree branch? 

Related to this is the matter of compatibilism. Is a fully physicalist account of why my arm stretched out COMPATIBLE with the view that (a) there is such a thing as an intangible MENTAL feeling of hunger, or perhaps an intangible decision to reach for the apple and (b) THAT intangible thing also counts -- along with any physicalist account one might produce -- as a cause of the plucking of the apple. 

Epiphenomenalism is the view that mental states exist but they don't CAUSE anything physical. 

Mind-body interactionist dualism contends that mental states do exist and through our bodies (perhaps through the pineal gland) they interact with the physical world.  There exists a complicated range of other possible beliefs about the mind-body issue. If we could decide whether and to what extent physical and mental causation of "voluntary" acts are compatible, we would have gone a long way to defining our positions on that.

Christenson and Baysan make the case that what is called "non-reductionist physicalism" about mind-body relations requires compatibilism about mental causation. That requires some additional explanation. 

Physicalism maintains that there are physical explanations for any physical fact. A human being reaches for an apple in the same way that a spider reaches for the trapped fly, and the explanation is fully physical in each case.

Reductive physicalism argues that there are no mental properties. Whatever exists, is physical. What we think of as mental can be reduced to the physical.

Non-reductive physicalism allows for there to be mental properties, and for the possibility that these cannot be fully reduced in physical terms. So our authors are saying that IF you want to hold to that view, you really ought to conceded that the mental and physical causative chains are mutually compatible. 

I think I may be an incompatibilist in this new sense, too, though, which means non-reductive physicalism as these authors understand it may not be quite my cup of tea. 



Comments

  1. So, ok---if it is accepted (or, recognized?) that mental states exist, but don't CAUSE physical actions, what does? Incompatibalism really confused my tablet---it just did not know what to do with the word. And it is only a machine. I understand some of the linguistic turns of philosophy. Try to work with, or around them. But, the smoke gets thick; the mirrors, hazy. Still, I try to make myself compatible with all that, understanding the terrain, as best I can.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Yes, I agree. Contemporary philosophers may have made some very complicated questions unnecessarily more so. But to get an idea of what (I think) is going on here, compare yourself to a frog. A frog likely never has the thought "That is a delicious fly." The frog simply reacts by instinct -- the tongue comes out, etc. Now, when I reach for an apple and it seems to me that I do so in response to the thought "that apple looks delicious," how different is my action from that of the flies? Incompatibilism allows for the answer, "considerably different!" Compatibilism requires the answer "not all that different." Whatever I say about my desire for the apple, in this view, must be compatible with a mechanistic account of how I reached for the apple in response to my perceptions -- its ripe redness, the smell of the apple blossoms, etc. At any rate I am happy to report that I have had a breakthrough, and I'll be making what I hope will be a clear short statement of my own view on mind-body issues next week.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Very good! Makes this entire subject comprehensible to me. Thanks for the effort.

      Delete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak