Skip to main content

W.D. Ross and pluralism




A couple years ago someone asked on QUORA whether W.D. Ross believe in an "absolute moral principle." 

I recently looked up that old question and my response to it, because I suspected it might shed some light on the matter of effective altruism I have discussed here of late.

I responded to the question about Ross as follows:

----------------------------------

I don’t believe that Ross would want you to think of any moral principle as absolute. His point was, to put it simply, that there are a plurality of moral principles and that they must be balanced against one another. If you want to think of the need to balance as itself an “absolute,” at least for Ross, you can. But that is more a matter of playing with words than of philosophizing. And yes, there is a difference.

Ross begins with what he calls “prima facie duties.” There are five of these: the duty to keep promises, the duty to repair such harms as we may have done, a duty to return services whence we have benefitted, a duty to promote a maximum of aggregate good, and a duty to refrain from harming others. In short form: fidelity, reparations, gratitude, benevolence, and non-maleficience.

He believes that these duties can come into conflict. That is why none of them is an absolute and they must be balanced against each other. It may be that my philanthropic plans have to be derailed in order to keep a promise. We often do give promises that have consequences that we did not consider when extending them. So: has benevolence come into conflict with fidelity here? what to do when that conflict arises? Ross has no absolute answer. It will depend on the specific situation, and on who you are at the moment when you are called upon to act one way or the other.... Some critics of Ross' position focus on the fourth duty, and ask why it doesn't -- why indeed it shouldn't -- swallow the others. Why aren't all our so-called prima facie duties just more or less round about ways of trying to make the world a better place? 

Yes, sometimes it is not clear whether one action or another will better advance this duty to make the world a better place. But (the critics will say) seeing that as a clash of duties does nothing to clarify the uncertainty. 

-----------------------------------------------

This stuck in my mind because the following comment section brought me into contact with David Friedman, an "august" figure for anarcho-capitalists.  I had an exchange with him in which he linked me to an updated statement of his views on medieval Iceland.

Anyway, it comes to front of mind NOW because effective altruists are in the position of the hypothetical critic of Ross I cited there. The trainwreck of really long-term applications of EA, and the rise of fall of Bankman-Fried into the bargain, might be considered Ross' reply to that hypothetical criticism. We don't have to make heroic sacrifices over speculations about the 33d century because, though those speculations may derive some tug from the duty of benevolence, they will regularly come into conflict with the other four duties in limiting ways. This is precisely the reason the others don't collapse into that one. 



Comments

  1. fascinating. I have read and thought about effective altruism and have written disbelieving thoughts on philanthropy. the discourse on Ross reminds me of a term that was bandied about years ago: *situational ethics*. I tentatively concluded then that SE was antithheticl to ethical and moral behavior. I still think that way. Ross' five key duties are also interesting because, in some sense, those camouflage(?) axiology and deontology---even EXCUSE good/bad, right/wrong thoughts and actions, depending on the intention attending the "situation". now, I could be wrong here, but people will make all sorts of excuses for lapses in *duties*, saying things like, sorry, I"ll better next time. well, sorry, but there is no integrity or altruism in that. the late Dan Dennett was right about mistakes. I support and agree with Ross' duty postulate, insofar as it is a portrayal of what was once called common decency. Others may not take that road---it demands a lot.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak