Skip to main content

Robert Merrihew Adams RIP


 A philosopher and theologian of some importance passed away on April 17. 

I refer to Robert M. Adams, long affiliated with the UNC Chapel Hill and with Rutgers.

Adams gave the Gifford lectures at the University of St. Andrews, Scotland, in 1998-99.  This alone makes him worthy of note. The Gifford lectures have become legendary as a regular contribution by one or another significant scholar, each presented originally as a lecture series over the course of an academic year though put eventually into book form. 

The mandate from the will of the late Lord Gifford is that the lectures should "promote the knowledge of God" in "the widest sense." This leaves a lot of room for interpretation. The philosophers and philosophy-adjacent scholars who have been honored with a Gifford invitation have included Josiah Royce, William James, Henri Bergson, Etienne Gilson, Samuel Alexander, Arthur Eddington, Alfred North Whitehead, Karl Barth, Reinhold Niebuhr, John Eccles, Simon Blackburn, Werner Heisenberg, Frederick Copleston, Hannah Arendt and many others.

And to that formidable list we may add Robert Adams, whose lectures became the basis for his book GOD AND BEING. 

Here is a link to an article he wrote that summarizes some of the themes of his Gifford lectures/book. 

God, Possibility, and Kant - CORE Reader

What I find especially of interest about it is a history-of-philosophy point.  There is a widespread impression that (a) Immanuel Kant is an extraordinarily important philosopher and (b) that the period of his importance begins when his "critical" period began -- when he read Hume's skeptical treatment of causation, was shocked out of what he himself called his "dogmatic slumber" and devoted himself to a detailed reply to Hume, which became in time is Critique of Pure Reason.  

Adams questioned that conventional wisdom. He believed, it appears, that the early Kant, the "pre-critical Kant," was important and valuable.  Adams believed, furthermore, that the pre-critical Kant offered an argument for the existence of God that might well be built upon and made tenable. The implication is that the critical turn in Kant's work was a backwards turn, not one to be celebrated. 

I find this fascinating.  

Rest in peace, Professor Adams.  

Postscript: In other decedent-philosopher news: Robert Kane has passed. I have quoted him frequently in this blog, whenever I discuss free will and incompatibilism. I will give him a proper farewell next week. 

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak