Skip to main content

Positions within the Philosophy of Science

Image result for quarks


Here's a link to a fascinating diagram that surely represents a lot of work and thought,

https://chrisblattman.com/2014/11/17/positions-philosophy-science/?fbclid=IwAR0N9hy9FqL7Oo4czEp7TZOQ2r2xczO2jpH6TTWS5lEWW7tS1zLFNM07xbs

I hope you'll each follow the link and look around at the diagram. I won't try to reproduce it here. I'd either have to make it prohibitively small or crop some of it. Instead, my visual here is a diagram of quarks fusing.

The underlying question behind the philosophy of science, as least as it is portrayed in this chart, is the following: is a "quark" (for example) a real thing -- part of the furniture of the universe, like the tree just outside my window -- or is it merely a useful postulate?

As you can see if you follow the link, the fellow who prepared the graph takes the distinction between realism and anti-realism to be fundamental. The distinction is represented by a blank space in the middle -- and both positions are represented as arrows moving away from that blank space.

Some philosophers are portrayed as bridging the gap. Quine, Putnam, and Poincare are each represented as on both sides of the central gap. I don't think this is supposed to represent any ambiguity in their positions, though: I suspect in each case the philosopher in question had different phases in his own development that warrant the different placement.

"Pragmatism" appears, as a generic term, on the right side of the gap, in between the large labels "constructive empiricism" and "instrumentalism." The two pragmatists most deeply tied to such questions, Peirce and Dewey, are separately represented. Both Peirce and Dewey are a little bit to the 'right' of generic Pragmatism: that is, they are presumably a little less inclined to realism.

I would imagine that the generic term "Pragmatism" is here used to refer to William James. He spoke to the issue in broad terms only in brief passages, which have a somewhat cryptic sound to them. That may be why he is not actually named.

James also spoke to issues of scientific method in his writings as a psychologist, but the issues in that field are not quite the same as the philosophy-of-physics stuff that appears mostly to motivate this graph.

I'll make one more brief observation. I had no idea what "NOA" was until I saw this chart, which portrays it as the rightwardmost edge of realism. So I looked it up. The initials stand for "natural ontological attitude," and the abbreviation was created by philosopher Arthur Fine. (Fine is also represented by name, and as bridging the central gap.)

I'll leave further research to you.




Comments

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak