Skip to main content

Truth value gluts

 


As I have discussed here before (notably in connection with the Vienna Circle), I believe there are limits to the applicability of the law of the excluded middle. 

One example: one can say with some plausibility that as recently as 1990 the validity of Fermat's last theorem was outside the scope of the law.  The answer was not only not known, there was no clear procedure for solving it. So ... it was neither true nor false until such a proof had been created (not discovered, if one is going to take this view: created).  

Likewise with the Riemann Hypothesis, still unsolved to this day, though it helpfully provides us with a striking image above. A gentlemen who regularly comments on math issues in Quora wrote recently, "There are several fields of mathematics which only make sense on the premise that the Riemann Hypothesis is true, and a handful of others which only make sense on the premise that it is false."  

My point though is that no such situation gets us to a truth value glut.  In the lingo of contemporary epistemology, such a contention gets us to a truth value gap. A situation in which we want to say that the Riemann Hypothesis is neither true nor false.  If we want to say it is both true AND false, we have a truth value glut. 

Bu why would we want to have a truth value glut? One view, advocated by Graham Priest, if I understand him, is that classical paradoxes are best dissolved by simply treating the key sentence as both true and false. "This sentence is false." Well ...is it? Yes. Well, then, it has to be true!  Yes, it is that as well.

There is an asymmetry between truth-value gaps and gluts. Gaps are proposed pending a solution -- they are proposed in order to be filled in.  Gluts are proposed AS solutions -- they are proposed in order to remain in place.      

Also, truth glut logic helps make metaphysical mysteries respectable.  There is a new work on Christian theology, Divine Contradiction, Oxford University Press, 2023, in which the author, Jc Beale, says that both of these propositions are true:

1) The Father is God,

2) It is not the case that the Father is God.

BTW, I don't get the notion that Beale calls himself "Jc Beale". Shouldn't it be "J.C. Beale"? I don't know, but apparently it isn't. Is it pronounced "Jack Beale"?  Or is it akin to the symbol that Prince adopted for himself, where unpronounceability was the point? 

Anyway, Beale thinks, sensibly enough, that these propositions cannot both be affirmed if one is eager to embrace the "law of the excluded middle." But rejecting that law is not enough to make these pair of affirmations work, either. A truth-value gap wouldn't help us with Trinitarianism. We need a truth-value glut.     

A believer presumably wants the first of those propositions to be true without further fuss, and the second of them to be both true and false. 

Comments

  1. Who is the Father (apart from whether he is God or not God)? The capitalization suggests that it is God, but that would make the two statements a tautology and a contradiction, respectively, and I doubt you intend that.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Big question. I'll try to draw upon my years at Catholic Sunday school classes. Even without that dubious benefit, you are surely aware that Catholics profess a belief in a God who consists of three persons: the Father, the Son, and the Holy Spirit. "Neque confundentes personas, neque substantiam separantes." That is the Latin for, "neither confounding the [three] persons, nor separating them in essence." Within this trinity, the Father is that person closely associated with Creation, and with the Law as given to Moses. Further, the Father is the one Person of this Trinity who is neither "begotten" nor a "procession" from any other person or persons. The Son is begotten of the Father (hence their respective names), the Holy Spirit proceeds from both the first two Persons. You can see why this all -- and I have just scratched the surface-- keeps theologians who care about logic ... busy.

      Delete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

A Story About Coleridge

This is a quote from a memoir by Dorothy Wordsworth, reflecting on a trip she took with two famous poets, her brother, William Wordsworth, and their similarly gifted companion, Samuel Taylor Coleridge.   We sat upon a bench, placed for the sake of one of these views, whence we looked down upon the waterfall, and over the open country ... A lady and gentleman, more expeditious tourists than ourselves, came to the spot; they left us at the seat, and we found them again at another station above the Falls. Coleridge, who is always good-natured enough to enter into conversation with anybody whom he meets in his way, began to talk with the gentleman, who observed that it was a majestic waterfall. Coleridge was delighted with the accuracy of the epithet, particularly as he had been settling in his own mind the precise meaning of the words grand, majestic, sublime, etc., and had discussed the subject with William at some length the day before. “Yes, sir,” says Coleridge, “it is a majesti

Five Lessons from the Allegory of the Cave

  Please correct me if there are others. But it seems to be there are five lessons the reader is meant to draw from the story about the cave.   First, Plato  is working to devalue what we would call empiricism. He is saying that keeping track of the shadows on the cave wall, trying to make sense of what you see there, will NOT get you to wisdom. Second, Plato is contending that reality comes in levels. The shadows on the wall are illusions. The solid objects being passed around behind my back are more real than their shadows are. BUT … the world outside the the cave is more real than that — and the sun by which that world is illuminated is the top of the hierarchy. So there isn’t a binary choice of real/unreal. There are levels. Third, he equates realness with knowability.  I  only have opinions about the shadows. Could I turn around, I could have at least the glimmerings of knowledge. Could I get outside the cave, I would really Know. Fourth, the parable assigns a task to philosophers

Searle: The Chinese Room

John Searle has become the object of accusations of improper conduct. These accusations even have some people in the world of academic philosophy saying that instructors in that world should try to avoid teaching Searle's views. That is an odd contention, and has given rise to heated exchanges in certain corners of the blogosphere.  At Leiter Reports, I encountered a comment from someone describing himself as "grad student drop out." GSDO said: " This is a side question (and not at all an attempt to answer the question BL posed): How important is John Searle's work? Are people still working on speech act theory or is that just another dead end in the history of 20th century philosophy? My impression is that his reputation is somewhat inflated from all of his speaking engagements and NYRoB reviews. The Chinese room argument is a classic, but is there much more to his work than that?" I took it upon myself to answer that on LR. But here I'll tak